Donate books to help fund our work. Learn more→

The Rudolf Steiner Archive

a project of Steiner Online Library, a public charity

The Fundamental Social Demand of Our Times
GA 186

13 December 1918, Dornach

I. The Transforming of Instinctive into Conscious Impulses

We have been studying from many points of view the social impulses of the age, of the present day and of the future. You will have seen, among the many and varied phenomena which these impulses bring forth, that there is one apparently fundamental tendency. Characterizing it to begin with in a more external manner, we may say: True it is that the most varied phenomena emerge, and the most varied demands are being made. Social and antisocial world-conceptions make their appearance. This or that action is taken, inspired by these social or antisocial world-conceptions. But if from the vantage-point now gained we put the question: “What is it that really underlies these things? What is it that is trying to work its way out to the surface in human destinies and human evolution?” Then (as I said, externally to begin with) we may characterize it as follows:—Man wants to have a social order, he wants to give the life of mankind in society a social structure within which, in harmony with the age of the spiritual soul, he may become conscious of what he is and knows himself to be as Man—in his human dignity, in his significance and force as Man. Within the social order, he wants to find himself as Man.

Formerly, impulses that were instinctive guided man to do, to think, to feel on one thing or another. In the present age—the age of the spiritual soul, which began in the fifteenth century and will last into the third millennium A.D.—these instinctive impulses are seeking to be transformed into conscious ones. And man will only be able rightly to introduce these conscious impulses into his life if in the course of this age he becomes more and more conscious of what he as Man is and can be within the social structure—the structure of Society or of the State or whatever it may be—in which he lives.

Spiritual Science, after all, is alone able to penetrate these things clearly, in the true direction of the age of the spiritual soul. Yet they emerge—as I have already indicated—they make their appearance here and there in a more or less tumultuous form, not only in the thoughts and opinions but in the events in which the men of the present day are living. It is characteristic, for example, to see what comes to expression in a recent speech by Trotsky. If you consider what I have just said about the desire to place Man in the very center of our World-conception, such words as Trotsky uses here will make an overwhelming, shattering impression upon you. He says:—“The communist or socialist doctrine has set itself, as one of its most important tasks, to attain at length on our old sinful Earth a state of affairs when men will cease to shoot at one another. Thus it is one of the tasks of Socialism or Communism to create a social order where for the first time man will be worthy of the name. We are wont to say with Gorki that the word Man strikes a proud and lofty note, yet in reality, looking over these three and three-quarter years of bloody murder, we would fain cry out: The sound of the word ‘Man’ is shameful and contemptible.”

At all events, you here see the question:—How can man become conscious of his human being, his human worth and human strength?—placed in a tumultuous way in the very center of attention at the beginning of a political speech. And, if you observe more closely, you will meet the same phenomenon in many people. What Spiritual Science realizes in a clearer way leads a shadowy existence in many human heads. Now this is a phenomenon which we shall only understand if we consider many things in the social thinking of the 5th Post-Atlantean Age which we have not studied closely enough as yet.

Truly, infinitely much has become different—quite suddenly—different since the time of the 15th century when the fifth Post-Atlantean Age began, following as it did upon the Fourth which then came to an end. (The Fourth, as you know, had begun in the 8th century B.C.). Men only fail to notice how radically the constitution of soul in civilized mankind was changed in the transition, for example from the 13th or 14th to the 15th or 16th century. I have told you of many phenomena in the realm of Art, in the realm of Thought and in other realms of life, in which you can recognize the change. Today we will consider another aspect—an aspect which is of peculiar importance for the forces which are working themselves out in the present and in the immediate future. We may truly say: It is only since the beginning of the 5th Post-Atlantean Age that men have consciously observed the public economic and industrial life as to the way it enters into the social structure. Previously, these things, of which men think consciously to-day, came forth more or less instinctively. It is only towards the 16th century that men begin consciously to raise the question: What is the nature of the order of political economy? What is the best kind of economic order? What are the laws that underlie it? It is from considerations of this kind that the impulses of the socialistic world-conception have evolved even to our own day. Formerly these things had been ordered more or less instinctively, from man to man, from association to association, from guild to guild, corporation to corporation, and even from realm to realm. Only since the rise of the modern form of State which itself dates back, approximately, to the 16th century, do we see this conscious thinking about economic questions!

Now when you turn your attention to such a phenomenon as this, you must remember the following important fact: So long as a thing works instinctively, it works with a certain sureness. Call it what you will, the Divine Order or the order of Nature, instincts are a force that works through all the evolution of mankind with a certain sureness, unshaken by thought. Uncertainty only begins from the moment when the things of life, in whose sphere the certainty of instincts was working hitherto, begin to be penetrated by human thought and reflection, human intellect. And only gradually, having gone through many and varied errors, does man regain in a conscious way that sureness and inner certainty which, under different conditions, he had in former times by instinct.

Of course we must not make the objection: let us then rather go back to instinct! The conditions have changed and under the altered conditions instinct would no longer be the right thing. Mankind is in the course of evolution, and evolution consists in passing from instinct to conscious life with respect to all these things. The demand that we should return to the old instinct would be no wiser than if someone who had reached the age of fifty suddenly resolved to return to the age of twenty.

Thus we see the beginning of conscious thought on questions of Political Economy towards and during the 16th century. Men direct their conscious attention to things that were hitherto experienced and lived-out instinctively in the social connections of mankind.

It is interesting to bring before our souls some at least of the thoughts and conceptions which men arrived at about the social order. Thus, to begin with, the Mercantilists, as they are called, appeared on the scene with certain ideas about the economic life of society. On closer examination, their conceptions appear entirely dependent on the legal and juridical ideas which had already arisen in public life. Armed with these conceptions they tried to understand the course and evolution of trade and of modern industry in its first beginnings. The ideas of the Mercantilists are dependent above all on the study of trade. But they are also influenced by other things, influenced by the fact that the modern, more absolutist form of monarchy, with all its bureaucratic officialdom, assumed its peculiar configuration in their time. Again, their conceptions are conditioned by the fact that large quantities of precious metals were imported into Europe through the discovery of America; and that the old form of economy was now replaced by that which deals in money. Such influences as these determined the ideas of the earliest Political Economists—the Mercantilists. It is evident from the ideas that they express that their effort was to conceive public economic life and social life on the model of the old forms of private economic intercourse. And as you know, for the old private economic intercourse there were the Roman juridical ideas of legal rights. These ideas, as I said, they are now carried forward. Within the framework of these legal conceptions they simply tried to extend the laws of private economic life into the sphere of public life.

Such ideas give rise to a peculiar result, and, as I said just now, it is interesting to trace the several points to which men directed the main attention of their thoughts as time went on. As a result of their ideas, the Mercantilists said to themselves: The essential thing in the economic life of any national community is to possess as large an equivalent as possible for the commodities circulating in Trade, and produced by Industry, within the given territory. In other words, their desire was to think out a social structure whereby as much money as possible should find its way into the country for which they were concerned. They saw the prosperity of the country in the amount of money it contained. “How then can we enlarge the prosperity of the country?” (For then they thought, the prosperity of the individual would also be enlarged as much as possible.) “How can we increase the country's prosperity?” By bringing about as far as possible that inner social economic structure whereby a large amount of money will circulate within the country and very little will flow from it to other countries. As much money as possible was to be concentrated in the given country.

Against this conception there then arose another, that of the Physiocrats. The latter took their start from the idea: Economic prosperity does not in reality depend on the amount of money that is kept within the country; it depends on the amount that is produced out of the land by human labor—on the quantity of goods produced by exploiting the resources of Nature. In effect, it is only an apparent prosperity that is achieved by the circulation of goods in Trade and by the accumulation of money which does not increase the real Prosperity. Here you see arising, in two successive theories of economics, two altogether different points of view. And this is what I would beg you to observe. For one might well believe that once one had studied these things, it should be quite easy to say what it is that conditions prosperity, and what is the best form of public economic life. But when you see that the men who think about these things, who even make it their profession to do so, arrive in course of time at the very opposite conclusions, you will no longer say that it is quite so easy.

The Physiocrats, laying their main stress on the production of goods by the tillage of the soil and the exploitation of Nature generally, came to the conclusion that one ought to leave men to themselves, for they would then be impelled by free competition to elaborate as much as possible out of the Nature-basis of existence. While the Mercantilists were more concerned in erecting Customs barriers and closing the country, so as to limit the outward flow of money and increase the national prosperity by keeping the money in the country, the Physiocrats came to the opposite conclusion. According to them, free export and import from one country to another was the very thing to enhance the exploitation of the soil over the whole Earth, and accordingly, the prosperity of every single country.

Thus at the very dawn of conscious thinking on economic matters you see these opposite and conflicting thoughts arise in manifold directions. We may now go on and observe the entry of a most influential theory of political economy, one that had an extraordinarily powerful influence on legislation, and a powerful influence too on the thoughts of economists themselves. I mean the theory of Adam Smith, who placed before himself this question above all: “How should we bring about a social structure such as to develop, in the best possible way, the welfare of the individual and at the same time the welfare of the community?” I will here emphasize one characteristic point. Adam Smith arrived at the idea that an entirely individualistic development of economic life is the best thing possible. He took his start from the idea that goods, the commodities we buy and sell—constituting after all the very substance of the national economy—are in effect the result of human labor. We may put it this way. Whenever we buy a thing, the thing we buy has come into existence through the performance of human labor. The piece of goods, the commodity is, as it were, crystallized human labor. And Adam Smith thought: Just because this was the foundation of economic life, prosperity will best be brought about if we do not hinder people through any kind of legislation from producing freely. The individual will do the best for the community if he does the best for himself. Roughly speaking, this is Adam Smith's idea: We shall do the very best for all mankind if we do the very best for ourselves, for then we shall best be able to deliver the goods. It will be best both for the individual and mankind to arrange the economic life in an individualistic way and not to erect hindrances by legislation or the like.

Such, my dear friends, is the whole direction of thought in all these theories of political economy. “What is the best way of arranging the social structure?” In this connection one idea may possibly occur to you and if so it may well seem to you the most important of all. It is a question which was not really clearly seen even by the Physiocrats. In all the systems of political economy of which I have spoken hitherto, they considered what is the best way of arranging and producing the economic structure of society. But as we follow up the thoughts that here emerge, we are reminded again and again that there is also another question, namely this: What is the essential purpose of this economic life? Its object cannot merely be to distribute whatever is available. Surely it must also see to it that something shall be available; that the necessary material goods shall really be produced. The point is, after all, to produce the necessary goods from the Earth. What then is the relation of man to the goods that are to be derived from the Earth? It was Malthus who first put forward conscious thoughts upon this question, and it must be said that his thought took a line which may well cause humanity considerable misgiving. The cardinal question which Malthus brings to light, and the view which he puts forward in answer to it, are by no means quite unfounded. He says: Let us consider the increase in the human population of the Earth. He believed, as many modern people do, that the population of the Earth is always increasing. Then let us consider the increase in the food-stuffs and means-of-life that are produced. We shall obtain a certain ratio. Malthus expresses it somewhat mathematically. He says: The increase in food-stuffs will take place in arithmetical, and the increase in population in geometrical, progression. I may make it clear by a few numbers. Let us assume that the increase in the food-stuffs produced is in the ratio 1, 2, 3, 4, 5. Then we shall have the corresponding geometrical ratio, 1, 4, 9, 16, 25. In other words, his idea is, the population will increase much faster than the available food-stuffs. Mankind in its evolution cannot escape the danger that a struggle for existence will arise, for in the last resort there will be far too many people in relation to the increase in the food-stuff. Thus he conceives the economic evolution of mankind from quite a different point of view, namely, from the aspect of the connection of man with the conditions of the Earth. He comes to the conclusion, or at least his followers come to the conclusion, that it is against the real line of evolution to practice much charity and welfare work for the poor, and the like. For by so doing we only encourage over-population, and this is harmful to the evolution of mankind. He even comes to the point of saying: Whosoever is weak in life, let us leave him unsupplied, unsupported, for it is necessary that the unfit should be weeded out. And he conceives other methods of which I will not speak at this point. I will but indicate their nature. He recommends especially the two-children system in order to counteract the natural tendency to over-population. Wars he regards as something that must necessarily arise in human evolution, because it is a tendency of nature for the population to increase far more rapidly than the means of life.

You see, it is a very pessimistic conception of the economic evolution of mankind which here appears upon the scene of history, nor can we say that much attention has been devoted in more recent times to this question: How is man connected with the Nature-basis of his economic life? In more recent times there is not even a clear consciousness that one ought to make investigations in this direction. For in the subsequent period attention was directed again and again to the social structure itself; to the way in which men should distribute what is available in order to attain the greatest possible prosperity. The question was not “How shall we derive as much as possible from the Earth?” It was more a question of distribution.

Along these lines of thought many different theories emerge, which is important to observe, since they prepare the way for the social and a socialistic thinking of the present day, which has led mankind already in a high degree into a kind of social chaos and will do so still more in the future, and from which it is essential to seek the right way of escape. One of these things I have just indicated, when I mentioned how distinctly there emerges, in Adam Smith for example, the idea: The commodity, the piece of goods that we buy, represents stored-up labor. Increasingly, as though by an inevitable process, there arose the thought: That which appears as a commodity can be regarded in no other way than as stored-up labor. This idea has dominated man to such an extent that it is one of the main motive forces in the proletarian thinking at the present time. For on the economic premises which I have characterized, there has entered the minds of the modern proletariat a keen vision of the fact that such as the economic order, such as the social structure is today, the labor-power of the worker who has no property, who can only bring the labor of his hands on to the market, is a commodity. Just as we buy any other things, so do we buy his labor-power from the proletarian worker.

Over against the question:—What am I in reality as Man?—the modern proletarian feels this as the thing that most oppresses him, and from this his social demands instinctively proceed. He does not want any part of him to be bought and sold. We may say: He appears to himself as though a man could sell his own hands and arms. This seems to him intolerable. No matter in what form the feeling finds expression, in Marxist or in revolutionary thought, or however we may call it, the underlying feeling is, “Other folk buy and sell commodities, but I am obliged to sell my labor power.”

My dear friends, it would be a simple error to object that other people too sell their labor. That is not true. In the social structures of the present day, it is really only the proletarian worker who sells his labor. For the moment [if] one is connected in any way at all with property, one ceases to sell one's labor power. Thus the bourgeois does not sell his labor, he buys and sells commodities. He may sell the products of his labor, but that is a different thing from selling one's labor. The modern proletarian has very keen and sharp ideas on these things, and if you know the thinking of the modern proletarian you will know that the significance of this concept the “proletarian laborer” is that he is one who sells his labor power. And you will know, moreover, how strongly this idea works as the real driving force in the proletarian thinking of today, from its most moderate to its most radical forms of experience. Anyone who is unable to read this out of the phenomena themselves, simply fails to understand this present time. And it is a sad thing how many people fail to understand it. It is through this that we go more and more deeply into confusion: men do not really try to understand their time.

That is the one thing. The other thing is this:—However modified by later, albeit somewhat instinctive points of view, a certain kind of thought has arisen in connection with what I have now characterized. We find this thought expressed in the idea of the Law of Wages. It is true that in the modern Proletarian thinking this idea no longer exists in the same radical form. Nevertheless we must know the form in which it was held, for instance, by Lasalle. For only then shall we perceive what exists in the present-day proletarian as a kind of residue of this idea. The so-called iron Law of Wages was clearly formulated by the economist Ricardo, and even in the middle of the last century Lasalle stood out for it with all energy. It is somewhat as follows. Under the social structure of today, with the form that Capital assumes in this social structure, he who is obliged to work as a proletarian can never receive beyond a certain maximum of wages for his labor. His wages will always fluctuate about a certain level. They cannot rise beyond it, nor can they descend beneath it. The objective facts make it necessary for a certain level of wages to be paid in the long run. The level of the worker's wages cannot rise beyond or descend below the maximum or if you will the minimum (it does not matter for the present purpose how we call it). They cannot depart from it to any considerable extent, and for the following reasons: so thought Ricardo. He says: let us assume that through some circumstance—a favorable period in Trade or the like—there would arise at any time an unusual increase in wages. What then would happen? The proletariat would suddenly receive higher wages. Their standard of life would be improved, they would attain a certain prosperity. Consequently it would be more attractive to seek for labor as a proletarian than under the preceding level of wages.

There will therefore be a larger supply of proletarian labor. Moreover, owing to their increased prosperity, the workers will multiply more quickly—and so on. In short, the supply will be increased. As a result, the laborer will be easier to obtain; and we shall therefore begin once more to underpay him. The wages will therefore fall back to their former level. Through the very rise in wages, phenomena are induced which causes them to fall again. Or let us assume that wages fall through any circumstance. Poverty and wretchedness will be the result and the supply of labor will be reduced. Workers will die more quickly, or they will get diseases. They will have fewer children. So the supply of labor power will be reduced, and this in turn will bring about an increase in wages. But the increase cannot go on essentially beyond the level of the iron law.

Of course, my dear friends, Ricardo, and Lasalle too, in propounding this iron Law of Wages, were thinking of the determination of wages in the purely economic process. Today, nay even twenty or thirty years ago, even proletarians, where one cited the iron Law of Wages in the history of economic science would reply: That is incorrect, there Ricardo and Lasalle were wrong. But this objection too is really incorrect. For Ricardo and Lasalle could only have meant that if the social structure is left to itself this iron Law of Wages will begin to work. It was just in order that it should not work, that Workers' Associations were founded and that the help and influence of the State was called into play. As a consequence the level of the Law of Wages was artificially raised. Thus whatever goes beyond the iron level is brought about by legislation or by associations or the like. The objection is therefore not really valid. You see, it all depends on the way in which we turn the thought.

Well, these things might of course be multiplied without limit. I only wanted to place them before you in order to show how the conscious thoughts of men on economic questions have gradually evolved during the age of the Spiritual Soul. The opinions of men were always dominant in the one direction or another. Some held the opinion that national prosperity would be greatest if the economic life were arranged on an individualistic basis, leaving the individual as free as possible. Others thought that this would put the weaker at a disadvantage; the weaker brethren must be supported by the assistance of the State or the association.

I should have to go on for a long time if I were to describe all the ideas that emerged as time went on. In many different regions of the Earth, i.e., of the civilized world, conceptions of political economy arose. Fundamentally speaking, it was the aim of all of them—those that I have characterized and many others—not only to study the nature of the social structure that has evolved in the world hitherto, but also to consider what is the best thing to do to the social structure in order that men may not have to live in poverty in order that they may have prosperity, and so forth. Economic science, in many of its representatives, did after all set out with the strong desire to better the economic life of the people. Utopian characters and such characters as the French Socialists Saint Simon for instance, Auguste Comte, Louis Blanc and others had this in view. Their thought was somewhat as follows: Hitherto, Society being left more or less to itself has evolved in such a way as to produce great differences between the poor and the rich, the well-to-do and the unhappy. This state of affairs must now be changed. To this end they studied the laws of economics and propounded the many varied ideas with a view to bringing about some kind of improvement. Naturally, in so doing, many of them set out entirely the idea that it should be possible to establish some kind of Paradise on Earth.

In the modern proletariat, however, the conscious thinking about the social structure assumes a special form. We have already spoken of the reason why the proletariat above all was predestined to develop these ideas. But there is one special aspect on which I now want to dwell a little further. True it is that what Karl Marx brought to expression in his book (and those which he wrote in collaboration with Engels) has been considerably modified since then. Yet the changes are small compared to the basic impulses which these thoughts contain. And though the statement only holds true in a modified form, nevertheless in general we can say: Throughout the countries of the civilized Earth, from the extreme West to Russia, the proletariat are dominated by the Marxist impulses, albeit no longer explicitly by the precise outlines of the Marxist thoughts. And the conscious thinking about the social structure appears in a quite peculiar form in this modern, Marxist, proletarian thinking.

The thoughts that we have today unfolded—those therefore which appear already in the bourgeois Political Economist since the beginning of the Age of Consciousness—are taken up into the socialist thinking, which, however, modifies and recasts them in the direction in which the worker out of the proletarian class must necessarily think them. And this is the peculiar thing:—The thought—“Within the modern capitalistic social structure, Man as a proletarian is obliged to sell his labor-power”—this thought however theoretically elaborated, becomes the driving force of proletarian thinking. And now the thought emerges: “How is it to be avoided; how is it to be made absolutely impossible for labor-power to be brought on to the market and sold like a commodity?” Needless to say this impulse is strongly influenced by the idea which is clearly formulated already in Adam Smith and others—the idea that in the commodity we but have to do with so much stored-up labor-power. It is an immensely plausible idea, and one that leads on to the logical conclusion:—“If this is so, what then can we do? If I buy a coat, the work that was done by the tailor, or whoever else took part in bringing the coat into existence, is there in the coat; it is stored-up labor.” Thus they never put the question in this way at all: “Can we separate the labor from the commodity?” But they take it as axiomatic, as an absolute matter of course, that the labor is inseparably bound up with the commodity. Hence they look for a social structure which shall make this inevitable economic fact, that the labor remains bound up with the product of the labor, as harmless as possible for the worker.

Under the influence of such ideas the belief arose that a just remuneration for labor can only be brought about in a certain sense, by making the means of production public property, i.e., by making the community itself in some way the owner of the means of production—of the machinery, the land and the means of transport and distribution. The question simply did not arise: “Can we make the commodity independent of the remuneration for labor?” but they put the question thus: “How can we bring about a just form of remuneration, assuming as an obvious axiom that the labor flows into the commodity?” That is how they put the question, and on this everything else depends. Indeed even the materialistic conception of economic science, the extreme “Materialist Conception of History” depends on this way of putting the question. I have already explained to you the materialistic conception of history, where the modern proletarian thinks: Everything that works within the civilization of mankind, all spiritual creation, all thought, all politics, in a word everything other than the economic processes themselves—is a mere super-structure, an ideology erected on the foundation of that which is worked-out economically. The economic life is the real thing. The way the human being is placed within the economic structure—this is the real thing in human life. The kind of thoughts he has result from his connections with the economic life. Thoroughly rigorous Marxists, like Franz Mehring for example, write in this fashion even about Lessing. (I only give this one example.) They ask: “What was the nature of the economic life in the second half of the 18th century? What were the methods of manufacture? What were the methods of purchase? What was the relation of the industrial life to the remainder of mankind? And as a consequence, what was the habit of men's thoughts? How did such a phenomenon as Lessing arise?” This individual personality, Lessing, with all the works that he produced, is explained out of the economic life of the second half of the 18th century! Kautsky and others like him even try to explain the appearance of Christianity from this point of view. They investigate the economic conditions at the commencement of our era. Certain conditions of production were holding sway. As a consequence, men began to unfold what these writers describe as a kind of communistic thinking, which was then christened by the name of Christ Jesus. The true, the real thing, was the economic order at the beginning of our era. Christianity is an ideology, a super-structure, a reflection as it were, of the economic order. There is nothing else than the economic order. All other things hover above it like a Fata Morgana, a mirror-image, an unreality, or at most (as I explained in earlier lectures) as something that reacts in turn upon the events of other kinds.

And now, the two things which I have described work conjointly. First there is the indignation at the fact that Man must submit to a part of himself, namely his labor-power, being treated as a commodity; and this works in conjunction with the Materialistic Conception, driving to its uttermost extreme, that the Economic is the only real thing in life.

Of course, men of today, not all, have given themselves up to this idea. But among the proletariat, millions and millions are more or less dominated by it. As to the rest, the non-proletarians, other customs have become fashionable among them in relation to these things of life. The things that are done in the proletariat are of course “not done” in the other classes. When proletarian workers have worked their eight or ten or sometimes even more than ten hours a day, they come together in the evening and discuss these questions, or they get lecturers and teachers to explain them. There are women's meetings too. Every individual one of them is seriously concerned as to the nature of the social structure, and in their way, they think about it seriously. They see to it that those who have thought about these things shall tell them their results. And so forth. In a word, they are well-informed; albeit in their own way, they are well-informed. In the next higher level of Society, which we call the bourgeoisie, you must admit this is not the case. When “the day's work is done”—let us put this phrase in inverted commas—they concern themselves with quite other things. With the proletariat they will concern themselves at most (and if they do this much, they make a great fuss about it) by letting it be played before them on the stage—dished up by some bourgeois pedant as dramatist or poet. But as to thinking any thoughts about the economic order of society, they leave this to the Professors of the Universities, that is their job, they will see to that all right! Needless to say, the people of this age are not believers in authority! Still, they swear by what the University professors have thought about these questions. What they say must of course be correct, for they are the experts, they are paid to do so by the proper authorities, they are the people appointed for the purpose.

Talking of these Professors, it is a curious school of economics that has lately been evolved. Nowadays, when they write their books, they call it the “Historic School.” They deal with the Mercantilists, the Physiocrats, Adam Smith, Socialism, Anarchism, and so on. And when they come to their own idea—well, that is the “Historic School.” They are more or less of this opinion: “However shall we arrive at any real thoughts as to how things should be done?” ... Truth to tell, they are helpless when they come to this. They cannot rouse in themselves a sufficient activity of thought: they cannot rise to ideas as to how we should set about it, to bring about a structure of society. To a comfortable bourgeois pedant like Lujo Brentano, or Schmeller, or Roscher, it simply does not occur to bring his thought into such activity. Their idea is: We must observe the phenomena just as the Natural Scientist does. Such a man then lets the phenomena take their course and studies them. He simply studies the historic evolution of mankind, or at most, the historic evolution of the ideas of men about their economic life. He describes what exists. The most he will do is, like Lujo Brentano—if he does not find it convenient to observe these things in his home country—to travel to a representative country of the economic life, to England, and make his investigations there. He will then describe what is the relationship of employer and employed in that country, and so forth. If there are rich people there he learns to know how they acquire credit, how Capital works. If there is poverty there, if there are those devoid of property, some of whom have more or less nothing to eat, he will describe it as the result of this or that circumstance. And at last such a man will say: After all, it is not the task of Science to show how things ought to evolve, but only to point out how they do evolve in fact.

Yet after all, what will become of a Science which deals with the things of practical life in this way, merely watching and observing how these things evolve? Truly it is as though I were about to train an artist and I said to him: You must go to as many artists as possible and observe—“This one paints well,” “that one paints badly,” and so on—but above all things, you yourself must do nothing at all! In such a sphere the thing becomes absurd at once. And yet, my dear friends, it is a true comparison. It is indeed enough to drive one out of one's skin—forgive the expression—when one begins to study—I cannot say what is done, but what is wasted and fooled away nowadays where they claim to apply “the scientific method” to economics and such things of life. For the result is absolutely nil, since if we go to the root of the matter, the very premises from which they start are abstract and unreal. At most there will arise from among their ranks the so-called “professional socialists” whose observation of existing things leads them to the conclusion: “Something must be done” and they then make Laws pretending to investigate or remove this or that distress.

This very helplessness has done much to bring about the present situation; and today it would be cowardice if we failed to point out the facts. Needless to say the public of today worships no authority at all. But the pretentious nonsense they believingly accept in this domain of life (and declare themselves satisfied!) is very largely to blame for the chaos that has come upon us. These are serious matters, and we must take hold of them in their true shape and form. For then, my dear friends, the question will emerge: What is it that is working still more deeply in all these things? Why has it all come about in this way? Why are such changing and wavering ideas at work in a realm of life that is of such cardinal importance to mankind?

Let us consider such an idea, illusory as it is but extraordinarily effective; let us consider the Marxist idea, however modified—it does not matter. It is in all essentials the idea of the professional minds of our time. Consider this idea: Only the economic life, only the economic structure is the real thing; everything else is ideology, super-structure, Fata Morgana. Truly, it is an extraordinary thing—this absolute unbelief in all that Man can produce by way of spiritual things, evolving out of the thoughts that have arisen since the dawn of the Age of the Spiritual Soul. Men are being diverted more and more to the things that are outwardly known, outwardly and tangibly present to their senses. All other things they flee from and avoid. The fact is that not only the social thoughts but the social feelings and in the last resort the social events of our time have evolved under the influence of this flight from the spirit, this avoidance of spiritual things. And they will continue to evolve under this influence, if the call for a true spiritual-scientific penetration of the facts is neglected.

What is the deeper underlying truth? It is this, my dear friends. We have entered into the age of the Spiritual Soul; we are in it since the 15th century. Through the very development of this age of the Spiritual Soul, through his pressing forward to the awakening of the Spiritual Soul, man is unavoidably approaching ever nearer and nearer to a point in his evolution where, through counter-instincts in his nature, he would fain take flight. It will be one of the most essential things for modern man to overcome this instinct of flight. At all costs he wants to flee from what he must none the less enter.

The other day, the last time I spoke to you here, I said: Over the various national regions, the West, the Middle Countries, and the East, the way man approached the Guardian of the Threshold, when he enters into the spiritual world, is differentiated. Now men are moving towards the conscious experience of such things, as that these experiences can be undergone consciously when they meet the Guardian of the Threshold; and more or less instinctively they must be undergone by human beings in the course of time, during the Age of the Spiritual Soul. Men are being pressed and driven to this experience when they face the Guardian of the Threshold. It is this which works in a special, albeit external form, like an impulse, like an instinctive urge, in the men of modern time. And it is this from which they flee. They are afraid to come whither they really ought to come.

This is a very law in the modern evolution of mankind. Take what I said before as an external characterization of the modern striving. Man strives to know what he is as Man, what he is worth as Man, what is his strength and potentiality as Man. Man strives to see himself as Man, to arrive at a picture of his own Being. But we cannot arrive at a picture of Man if we are determined to remain within the world of the senses, for he is no mere physical being. In times of instinctive evolution, when one does not ask for a picture of Man, when one does not ask what is the dignity and strength of Man, one may overlook this fact—that to know Man one must transcend the world of the senses and gaze into the spiritual world. But in our age of consciousness, we must make acquaintance, at any rate in one form or another, be it only intellectually, with the super-sensible world. The same thing that the Initiate has to overcome consciously is working in our age unconsciously. Unconsciously as yet, there lives in our contemporaries, and in the men whose social thoughts I have described today, this fear of the Unknown—the Unknown which they are nonetheless being driven to observe. Fear, cowardice, lack of courage, is dominating the humanity of today. And if it is declared: “Economic life is the tangible thing which determines all other things,” this view itself has arisen simply through the fear of the invisible and the intangible. This they will not approach, they will avoid it at all costs, and so they lyingly transform it into an ideology, a Fata Morgana. The modern world-conception, my dear friends, is born of fear and terror in relation to those points which I have characterized. However outwardly courageous some of those within the stream of the modern social world-conception may show themselves to be, they are afraid of the Spiritual, which must meet them in one form or another, and in whose domain, after all, they long to know the human being. But they are afraid of it; like cowards, they recoil from it.

The things must be seen from this point of view. For the modern man must learn to know three things, inasmuch as he is led quite naturally to these three—differentiated in West, Middle and East, as I described last time. Quite naturally, in one form or another, he is led to these three things. Though only the Initiate beholds what is present in these points, yet in the course of time, every human being who seeks to penetrate and understand the social structure must feel them, sense them, receive them at least into his intellect.

In the first place the modern man must gain a clear feeling, or at least a clear intellectual conception, of those forces of the Universe which are the forces of decline and destruction. The forces to which we are fond of turning our attention (and for the very fondness, we delude ourselves about them) are of course the upbuilding forces above all others. We always want to build and build. But in the world there is not only evolution or upbuilding, there is also devolution, demolition. We ourselves bear the process of demolition within us; our evolved nervous system, our brain system, is perpetually engaged in demolition or destruction. With these forces of destruction man must make himself acquainted. With unprejudiced and open mind he must say to himself: Along the very path that unfolds in the age when the Spiritual Soul shall awaken fully, the forces of destruction are most active. When suddenly they concentrate or consolidate; then such a thing arises as in the last four and a half years. Then there appears to mankind in a concentrated form what in any case is always there. But this must not remain unconscious and instinctive: it must become a fully conscious thing, above all in the present age. The destructive forces, the forces of death, the paralyzing forces—how gladly would man turn his face away from them! But in so doing he only blinds himself. In fleeing from the destructive forces he learns not to cooperate in real evolution.

The second thing with which man must make himself acquainted and from which again he flees is this, my dear friends: In the present age of Intellectual evolution—that is to say, in the evolution of the Age of the Spiritual Soul, it is absolutely necessary for man to seek within himself as it were a new center of gravity of his own being. Instinctive evolution gave him even in his thought a center of gravity. He imagined that he stood fast on the views, the opinions, the ideas that came to him through the blood or through descent or in some other way. Henceforth man can do this no longer. He must free himself from these things on which he formerly stood so fast and firm, which arose in him instinctively. He must take his stand, as it were, at the edge of the abyss. He must feel beneath him the void of the abyss. He must find within himself the central point of his being. Man is afraid to do this, he recoils from the task.

And the third thing, my dear friends, is this: Man must learn to recognize the full power of the impulse of self-seeking, the impulse of egoism. Our age is destined to make it fully clear to man to what an extent, if he lets himself go, he is a selfish being. To overcome egoism, we must first have probed and realized all the sources of egoism that are there in human nature. Love only arises as the counterpart to self-love. We must cross the abyss of selfishness if we would learn to know that social warmth which has to penetrate the social structure of the present and the future; if we would learn to know it, above all, not only in theory but in full practice. And to approach this feeling—which the Initiate sees with fully conscious clarity, when face-to-face with the Guardian of the Threshold as he enters into the sense-world—this again fills man with fear. But there is no other way of entering into the age which must necessarily bring forth a social structure, than by a Love which is not self-love, which is a true Love for other men and interest in other men. Men feel this as a burning fire, as something that would consume them and take their own being from them, inasmuch as it deprives them of self-love, or the right to self-love. Even as they flee the super-sensible, of which they are afraid because it is to them an unknown region, so do they flee from Love, because it is to them a burning fire. And even as they bind their eyes and shut their ears to the truth of the super-sensible, when in the Marxism and in the misguided proletarian thinking of today they keep repeating that all things must be based on the tangible and the material—even as in this domain they go after the very opposite of that which lies in the real tendency of human evolution—so do they also in the realm of Love. Even in the catch-words and slogans this finds expression. They set up idealism, the very opposite of what really lies in the evolution of mankind and must be striven after.

Already in 1848, when Karl Marx's Communist Manifesto—the first and most significant declaration of the modern proletarian conception of life—was published, we find in it the words which are now printed as a motto on almost every socialistic book or pamphlet: “Proletarians of all lands, unite!” If we have but a little sense for realities, we are bound to pronounce a precise if strange and paradoxical judgment upon these words. What does it mean to say “Proletarians of all lands, unite!” It means, Work together, work with one another, be brothers, be comrades one to another! That is nothing else than Love. Let Love sway among you. Tumultuously the tendency arises—yet how does it arise?—Proletarians, you must be conscious that you are a class apart from the rest of mankind! Proletarians, hate the others who are not proletarians! Let hate be the impulse of your Union. In a strange way, wedded together, we here have Love and Hate—a striving for union out of the impulse of hatred, the very opposite of union. The people of today only fail to notice such a thing as this, because they are so far from connecting their thoughts with reality. Yet in truth this thought represents the very fear of Love, which Love, though it is striven for, is at the same time avoided, because they are afraid and recoil from it as from a consuming fire.

Only through Spiritual Science can we come to know the realities. Only through Spiritual Science can we perceive what is really working in the present time; what we must indeed perceive and recognize if we would take our place with real consciousness in this our time. It is by no means a simple matter to perceive all that is throbbing in the humanity of today. To do so, Spiritual Science is necessary. This should never be forgotten. And he alone stands rightly within this our spiritual movement, who knows how to take these things sufficiently in earnest.

Achter Vortrag

Sie werden aus den verschiedenen Betrachtungen, die wir in der letzten Zeit angestellt haben über die sozialen Impulse der neueren Zeit, der Gegenwart und der nächsten Zukunft, ersehen haben, daß in den mancherlei Erscheinungen, die aus diesen Impulsen heraus zutagetreten, sich eines wie eine Grundtendenz geltend macht, allerdings eine Grundtendenz, welche den Verlauf zunächst sehr äußerlich charakterisiert. Wir können sagen: Gewiß, die mannigfaltigsten Erscheinungen treten auf, die mannigfaltigsten Forderungen werden aufgestellt; soziale und antisoziale Weltanschauungen treten auf. Dies oder jenes wird getan aus solchen sozialen und antisozialen Weltanschauungen heraus. Wenn man aber von dem Gesichtspunkte aus, den wir nun gewonnen haben, zusammenfassen will mancherlei in die Frage: Was liegt denn eigentlich zugrunde, was will sich denn da an die Oberfläche der Menschengeschicke und der Menschenentwickelung arbeiten? - so wird man, allerdings zunächst äußerlich, die Sache so charakterisieren können: Der Mensch will auch eine soziale Ordnung haben, er will dem gesellschaftlichen Zusammenleben eine soziale Struktur geben, innerhalb welcher er sich, angemessen unserem Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele, bewußt werden kann, was er in seiner Würde als Mensch, in seiner Bedeutung als Mensch, in seiner Kraft als Mensch, was er als Mensch wissen kann. Er will sich als Mensch finden in dieser sozialen Ordnung. Diejenigen Impulse, die früher instinktiv waren, die haben den Menschen angeleitet, dies oder jenes zu tun, dies oder jenes zu denken, zu empfinden. Diese instinktiven Impulse wollen sich in bewußte Impulse verwandeln. Diese bewußten Impulse im Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele, das im fünfzehnten Jahrhundert seinen Anfang genommen hat und bis ins vierte Jahrtausend währen wird, wird der Mensch nur dann richtig in sein Leben hereinbringen können, wenn er sich immer mehr in diesem Zeitalter bewußt wird, was er als Mensch ist und als Mensch vermag auch innerhalb der sozialen Struktur, in der er gesellschaftlich, staatlich oder dergleichen lebt.

Ich habe schon angedeutet, daß dasjenige, was ja doch im Sinne dieses Bewußtseinszeitalters nur von der Geisteswissenschaft richtig, klar durchschaut werden kann, daß das in mehr oder weniger tumultuarischer Art da oder dort zum Vorschein kommt, sowohl in den Ansichten, in den Gedanken der Menschen, als auch in den Ereignissen, in denen der Mensch in der Gegenwart lebt. Es ist zum Beispiel recht charakteristisch, ich möchte sagen erschütternd charakteristisch, was in einer Rede zum Ausdruck kommt, die Trotzki gehalten hat. Wenn Sie das nehmen, was ich jetzt über den Willen, den Menschen in den Mittelpunkt der Weltanschauung zu stellen, gesagt habe, so werden Sie solche Worte, wie sie Trotzki sagt, als etwas Erschütterndes vernehmen. Er sagt: Die kommunistische Lehre oder die sozialistische Lehre hat sich als eine ihrer wichtigsten Aufgaben gestellt, auf unserer alten sündigen Erde eine solche Lage zu erreichen, daß die Menschen aufeinander zu schießen aufhören werden. Eine der Aufgaben des Sozialismus oder des Kommunismus ist, eine solche Ordnung zu schaffen, bei welcher der Mensch zum ersten Male seines Namens würdig sein wird. Wir sind gewohnt, zu sagen, das Wort «der Mensch» klinge stolz. Bei Gorki ist gesagt: Der Mensch, das klingt stolz. - In Wirklichkeit aber, wenn man diese drei dreiviertel Jahre des blutigen Mordens überblickt, so möchte man ausrufen: Der Mensch, das klingt schändlich!

Jedenfalls sehen Sie hier tumultuarisch auch diese Frage: Wie kann sich der Mensch seines Menschenwesens, seines Menschenwertes und seiner Menschenkraft gleichsam bewußt werden? - gleich im Anfange einer programmatischen Rede in den Mittelpunkt einer Betrachtung gerückt. Und so werden Sie, wenn Sie genauer zusehen, bei vielen ‘ Menschen der selben Erscheinung begegnen. Man versteht diese Erscheinung nur - ich meine jetzt die Art, wie das, was man durch Geisteswissenschaft klarer einsieht, unklar in den Köpfen spukt -, man versteht dieses Spuken, diese Erscheinung nur, wenn man auch mancherlei, was wir noch weniger betrachtet haben, mit Bezug auf das soziale Denken des fünften nachatlantischen Zeitraums ins Auge faßt. Eigentlich wird ungeheuer vieles anders, und zwar mit einem gewissen Sprung anders, seit jener Zeit, wo sich dieser fünfte nachatlantische Zeitraum im fünfzehnten nachchtistlichen Jahrhundert an den vierten, der damals endete, anreiht — der, wie Sie wissen, im achten vorchristlichen Jahrhundert begonnen hat. Die Menschen merken nur nicht, wie sich eigentlich die seelische Konstitution der zivilisierten Menschheit beim Übergange zum Beispiel aus dem dreizehnten, vierzehnten in das fünfzehnte, sechzehnte Jahrhundert radikal geändert hat. Ich habe Ihnen ja auf künstlerischem Gebiete, auf dem Gebiete des Gedankens, auf anderen Gebieten mannigfaltige Erscheinungen angeführt, aus denen Sie diese Änderung ersehen können. Heute wollen wir noch etwas ins Auge fassen, was ganz besonders für die Kräfte, die in der Gegenwart und der nächsten Zukunft spielen, von Bedeutung ist. Eigentlich kann man sagen, daß in bewußter Weise das öffentliche wirtschaftliche Leben, das öffentliche nationalökonomische Leben, wie es sich in die soziale Struktur hineinstellt, erst seit dem Beginne des fünften nachatlantischen Zeitraums beobachtet wird. Vorher war das, worüber die Menschen heute nachdenken, mehr oder weniger instinktiv in die Erscheinung getreten. Im Grunde fängt man erst gegen das sechzehnte Jahrhundert zu an, bewußt die Frage aufzuwerfen: Was ist Volkswirtschaftsordnung? Was ist die beste Volkswirtschaftsordnung? Welche Gesetze liegen der Volkswirtschaftsordnung zugrunde? — Und aus diesen Betrachtungen entwickeln sich dann die Impulse der sozialistischen Weltanschauung bis heute. Früher waren diese Dinge mehr oder weniger instinktiv geordnet worden, von Mensch zu Mensch, von Assoziation zu Assoziation, von Innung zu Innung, von Korporation zu Korporation, oder auch wohl von Reich zu Reich. Erst mit dem Heraufkommen des modernen Staatsgebildes, das ja ungefähr auch erst seit dem sechzehnten Jahrhundert datiert, sehen wir das Nachdenken über wirtschaftliche Fragen.

Nun dürfen Sie, wenn Sie auf so etwas den Blick richten, folgendes nicht außer acht lassen. Sie müssen sich klar sein darüber: Solange etwas instinktiv wirkt, wirkt es mit einer gewissen Sicherheit. — Nennen Sie es «göttliche Ordnung», nennen Sie es «Naturordnung», wie Sie wollen, Instinkte sind etwas, was mit einer gewissen Sicherheit durch die Menschheitsentwickelung hindurch wirkt, woran sich mit Gedanken nicht rütteln läßt, respektive woran mit Gedanken nicht gerüttelt wird. Und das Unsichere beginnt erst dann, wenn dieselben Gegenstände, auf deren Gebieten vorher die Sicherheit der Instinkte gewirkt hat, nun durchdrungen werden von dem menschlichen Nachdenken, von dem menschlichen Intellekt. Und erst nach und nach gewinnt der Mensch — man kann sagen, wenn er die mannigfaltigsten Irrtümer durchgemacht hat -, in bewußter Art dann jene Sicherheit, die er vorher für andere Verhältnisse durch den Instinkt gehabt hat.

Man darf natürlich dagegen nicht einwenden: Also kehre man lieber zum Instinkt zurück. Die Verhältnisse haben sich geändert, und unter den geänderten Verhältnissen würde der Instinkt nicht mehr das Richtige sein. Außerdem ist die Menschheit in einer Entwickelung und geht mit Bezug auf diese Dinge eben vom Instinkt zum bewußten Leben über. Die Forderung, man sollte wieder zu den alten Instinkten zurückkehren, wäre etwa ebenso gescheit, wie wenn jemand, der fünfzig Jahre alt ist, plötzlich beschließen wollte, wiederum zwanzig Jahre alt zu werden. - Da sehen wir, wie also gegen das sechzehnte Jahrhundert zu und im sechzehnten Jahrhundert das volkswirtschaftliche Denken beginnt. Man richtet den bewußten Blick auf Erscheinungen, die früher innerhalb des Menschheitszusammenhanges instinktiv erlebt worden sind.

Es ist interessant, wenigstens einige der Gedanken, der Vorstellungen, die sich die Menschen über die soziale Ordnung gemacht haben, vor die Seele zu führen. Da traten zum Beispiel zuerst auf mit gewissen Vorstellungen über das wirtschaftliche soziale Leben die sogenannten Merkantilisten. Ihre Vorstellungen sind eigentlich ganz abhängig von den Rechtsvorstellungen, die man sich vorher in juristischer oder sonstiger Beziehung im öffentlichen Leben gemacht hat, und mit diesen Vorstellungen versuchen sie den Verlauf, den Werdegang des Handels und der aufkeimenden Industrie zu verstehen. Diese Vorstellungen der Merkantilisten sind vor allen Dingen abhängig von der Betrachtung von Handel und Industrie. Aber sie sind auch beeinflußt von anderen Dingen, sie sind beeinflußt davon, daß die moderne, mehr absolutistisch geartete Monarchie mit ihrem Gefolge, dem Beamtenstaat, damals ihr besonderes Gepräge erhalten hat. Die Vorstellungen sind dadurch bedingt, daß durch die Entdeckung Amerikas viel Edelmetall in Europa eingeführt worden ist, daß an die Stelle der alten Wirtschaft die Geldwirtschaft getreten ist. Durch solche Dinge sind die Vorstellungen der ersten Volkswirtschaftslehrer, der Merkantilisten beeinflußt. Diesen Leuten kam es nach den Vorstellungen, die sie sich gebildet haben, darauf an, die öffentliche Wirtschaft, das öffentliche soziale Zusammenleben nach dem Muster der alten Privatwirtschaft zu denken. Und für die alte Privatwirtschaft hatte man ja die alten römischen juristischen Vorstellungen. Wie gesagt, die setzte man fort, nach denen hatte man einfach zu erweitern gesucht die Gesetze der Privatwirtschaft in das öffentliche Leben hinein.

Diese Vorstellungen haben ein eigentümliches Resultat gezeitigt, und es ist nicht uninteressant, zu verfolgen, auf was die Leute nach und nach in ihren Gedanken das Hauptaugenmerk richten. Sie haben das Resultat erzeugt, daß sich die Merkantilisten gesagt haben: Das Wesentliche einer Volkswirtschaft, einer Volksgemeinschaft beruht darauf, daß man möglichst viel Äquivalent hat für die durch Handel umzusetzende und durch die Industrie zu erzeugende Ware innerhalb eines volkswirtschaftlichen Territoriums. Mit anderen Worten, den Leuten kam es darauf an, solch eine soziale Struktur auszudenken, durch welche möglichst viel Geld in das Land kam, das sie gerade ins Auge faßten. In dem vorhandenen Gelde sahen sie den Wohlstand dieses Landes. Und wie kann man den Wohlstand dieses Landes, in dem dann auch der Wohlstand des einzelnen, meinten sie, der denkbar größte sein wird, groß machen? Dadurch, daß man möglichst eine solche innere Struktur dieses Landes herbeiführt, wodurch viel Geld im Lande zirkuliert, und wodurch auch wenig Geld von diesem Lande nach andern Ländern abfließt, so daß möglichst viel Geld im Lande konzentriert wird.

Gegen diese Anschauung erhob sich dann eine andere, die man die physiokratische Anschauung nennt. Diese Anschauung ging von dem Gedanken aus: Auf die Menge des Geldes, die in einem Lande zusammengehalten wird, kommt es eigentlich nicht an mit Bezug auf den Wohlstand, sondern es kommt darauf an, wieviel man durch Arbeit aus dem Boden herausarbeitet, wieviel man durch die Ausnützung der Naturkräfte an Gütern gewinnt. Mit der Zirkulation der Güter im Handel und mit der Ansammlung von Geld wird eigentlich im wesentlichen nur etwas Scheinbates erreicht. Es wird nicht der Wohlstand wirklich erhöht.

Sie sehen da in zwei aufeinanderfolgenden Anschauungen über die Volkswirtschaft zwei ganz verschiedene Gesichtspunkte auftreten. Darauf bitte ich Sie Ihr Augenmerk zu richten. Denn man könnte sehr leicht glauben, daß es außerordentlich leicht ist, wenn man das nur gelernt hat, zu sagen, wodurch der Wohlstand bedingt wird, welches die beste Art von Volkswirtschaft ist. Wenn Sie sehen, daß die Menschen, die darüber nachdenken, die sich das Nachdenken darüber sogar zum Beruf machen, zu entgegengesetzten Anschauungen im Laufe der Zeit kommen, so werden Sie nicht mehr sagen, daß es eine so ganz leichte Sache ist, sich Gedanken über diese Dinge zu machen.

Dadurch, daß die Physiokraten auf die Erzeugung der Güter durch die Bearbeitung des Bodens, der Natur überhaupt, den Hauptwert legten, kamen sie dann zu der Konsequenz, daß man eigentlich die Menschen sich selbst überlassen müsse, damit sie durch die freie Konkurrenz dazu getrieben würden, möglichst viel herauszuarbeiten aus der Naturgrundlage des Daseins. Haben die Merkantilisten mehr darauf gesehen, Zölle aufzurichten, die Länder nach außen abzuschließen, damit der Geldabfluß nicht zu groß ist und der Volkswohlstand erhöht wird durch das Zusammenhalten des Geldes im Lande, so kamen die Physiokraten zu der entgegengesetzten Anschauung, daß gerade, wenn man frei von einem Lande in das andere aus- und einführt, die Kraft in der Ausnützung des Bodens über die ganze Erde hin erhöht wird, und damit auch der Wohlstand des einzelnen Landes. Sie sehen, es treten gleich in der Morgenröte des bewußten Denkens über volkswirtschaftliche Dinge nach den verschiedensten Richtungen hin entgegengesetzte Gedanken auf.

Wir können dann weiter verfolgen, wie eine einflußreiche Anschauung auf volkswirtschaftlichem Gebiete Platz greift, die eigentlich ungeheuer intensiv die Gesetzgebungen beeinflußt hat, aber auch die Gedanken, die sich die Volkswirtschafter über diese Dinge gemacht haben. Das ist die Anschauung des Adam Smith, der namentlich die Frage sich vor die Seele rückte: Wie führt man eine soziale Struktur herbei, welche geeignet ist, den Wohlstand des einzelnen und den Wohlstand des Ganzen in der bestmöglichen Weise zu gestalten? — Adam Smith kam eigentlich — wir wollen auf einen charakteristischen Punkt dabei hinweisen - zu der Anschauung, daß die völlig individuelle Ausgestaltung der Volkswirtschaft das Allerbeste sei. Er ging ja davon aus, daß Güter, Waren, die ja schließlich den Inhalt der Volkswirtschaft ausmachen, die man zu kaufen und zu verkaufen hat, eigentlich das Ergebnis menschlicher Arbeit seien. Man könnte sagen, seine Anschauung war diese: Wenn man irgend etwas kauft, so ist das dadurch zustandegekommen, daß menschliche Arbeit verrichtet worden ist. Also ist gewissermaßen das Gut, die Ware, kristallisierte menschliche Arbeit. Und er meinte, daß der Wohlstand gerade wegen dieser Grundlage der Volkswirtschaft dadurch am besten herbeigeführt wird, daß man die Leute durch irgendwelche Gesetzgebungen nicht hindere, frei zu produzieren. Der einzelne wird gerade für die Gesamtheit dann das Beste leisten, wenn er für sich selber das Beste leistet. Adam Smith ist ungefähr der Anschauung, daß man auch für die gesamte Menschheit das Beste leiste, wenn man für sich das Beste leistet. Man kann dann am besten die Sachen abgeben und leistet für die Menschheit das Beste, wenn man für sich das Beste leistet. Es ist für den einzelnen und für die Menschheit am besten, wenn man individualistisch die Volkswirtschaft einrichtet, wenn man nicht durch Gesetzgebung besondere Hemmungen und dergleichen aufrichtet.

Nun sehen Sie, die ganze Richtung des Gedankens geht bei solchen Volkswirtschaftslehrern darauf hin: Wie richtet man die soziale Struktur am besten ein? — Nun aber wird Ihnen dabei vielleicht eine Frage kommen, die Ihnen als die wichtigste dünken könnte, die ja in ihrer Eigenart auch von den Physiokraten nicht ganz klar ins Auge gefaßt wird. Es wird nachgedacht in den volkswirtschaftlichen Systemen, von denen ich bisher gesprochen habe, wie man am besten die volkswirtschaftliche Struktur herbeiführen kann. Allein die Verfolgung dieser Gedanken, die hier zutagetreten, die erinnert einen doch immer wieder daran, daß da auch die andere Frage da ist, die Frage: Was will denn eigentlich die ganze Volkswirtschaft? — Sie will doch nicht nur, sie kann wenigstens nicht nur verteilen wollen, was da ist, sondern sie muß doch auch darauf sehen, daß etwas da ist, daß materielle Güter wirklich produziert werden. Es kommt ja auch darauf an, daß man der Erde Güter abgewinnt. Wie steht das Verhältnis des Menschen zu den Gütern, die der Erde abgewonnen werden? Darüber hat eigentlich erst Malthus bewußte Gedanken aufgestellt, und zwar liefen seine Gedanken in einer Bahn, die im Grunde genommen schon den Menschen bis zu einem gewissen Grade bedenklich machen kann. So ganz unbegründet ist es durchaus nicht, was als eine Kardinalfrage, und was als eine Anschauung über diese Kardinalfrage Malthus gerade zutage gefördert hat. Er sagte: Wenn man überblickt die Bevölkerungszunahme der Erde - er war der Ansicht, der ja viele moderne Menschen sind, daß die Bevölkerung der Erde immer zunimmt -, und wenn man überblickt die Zunahme der geförderten Nahrungsmittel, der geförderten Lebensmittel, so stellt sich ein Verhältnis heraus. Und Malthus drückt es etwas mathematisch aus, indem er sagt: Die Zunahme der Lebensmittel geht in arithmetischer, die Zunahme der Menschen in geometrischer Progression vor sich. — Ich kann Ihnen vielleicht durch ein paar Zahlen dies klar machen. Nehmen wir an, das Verhältnis der Nahrungsmittelzunahme ist 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, so würden wir das geometrische Verhältnis haben: 1, 2, 4, 8, 16. Er meint mit anderen Worten, die Bevölkerung nimmt viel schneller zu, als die Nahrungsmittel zunehmen. Er ist also der Ansicht, die Entwickelung der Menschheit kann der Gefahr gar nicht entgehen, daß Kampf ums Dasein eintritt, und daß endlich viel zuviele Menschen da sind im Verhältnis zur Nahrungsmittelzunahme. Also er faßt die volkswirtschaftliche Entwickelung der Menschheit von einem ganz anderen Gesichtspunkte aus ins Auge; von dem Gesichtspunkte des Zusammenhanges des Menschen mit den Erdenverhältnissen. Er kommt dazu, oder wenigstens seine Anhänger kommen dazu, daß es eigentlich gegen die Entwickelung spricht, viel Armenpflege und dergleichen zu treiben, denn dadurch züchtet man nur die Übervölkerung,; und das ist der Menschheitsentwickelung schädlich. Er kommt sogar dazu, zu sagen: Derjenige, der schwach ist im Leben, den lasse man ununterstützt, denn es kommt darauf an, daß die Unzulänglichen im Leben ausgemerzt werden. - Er versucht dann noch andere Mittel, von denen ich hier nicht sprechen will, ich kann es nur andeuten. Das Zweikindersystem sucht er namentlich zu empfehlen, um die Naturtendenz der Übervölkerung hintanzuhalten. Kriege betrachtet er als etwas, was notwendig in der Menschheitsentwickelung auftreten muß, weil eben die Naturtendenz vorhanden ist, daß die Bevölkerungszunahme eine weitaus schnellere ist als die Lebensmittelzunahme.

Sie sehen, eine recht pessimistische Anschauung über die wirtschaftliche Menschheitsentwickelung tritt da in die Geschichte ein. Man kann nicht sagen, daß diese Frage: Wie hängt der Mensch mit der Naturgrundlage seiner Wirtschaft zusammen? — sehr viel Pflege in der neueren Zeit erfahren hat. Nicht einmal ein klares Bewußtsein, daß nach dieser Richtung auch geforscht werden sollte, ist bei den Menschen der neueren Zeit vorhanden. Dann wurde gewissermaßen immer wieder hingewiesen auf die soziale Struktur selbst, auf die Art und Weise, wie die Menschen das, was da ist, zu verteilen haben, damit sie möglichst großen Wohlstand erzielen; nicht, wie man aus der Erde heraus möglichst viel schafft, sondern mehr auf die Verteilung ging die Frage.

Nun, im Laufe der Gedankengänge treten da verschiedene Dinge auf, die zu beachten wichtig ist, weil sie das soziale und sozialistische Denken der Gegenwart vorbereiten, das schon bis zu einem hohen Grade die Menschen hineingeführt hat und noch weiter hineinführen wird in eine Art von sozialem Chaos, aus dem der richtige Ausweg eben ganz notwendigerweise gesucht werden muß. Eines habe ich gerade schon angedeutet, daß zum Beispiel bei Adam Smith deutlich der Gedanke zutagetritt, dasjenige, was man als Gut kauft, die Ware, sei aufgespeicherte Arbeit. Und gewissermaßen bildet sich heraus wie etwas, was einer Naturnotwendigkeit entspricht, der Gedanke: Man kann dasjenige, was als Ware auftritt, gar nicht anders betrachten, denn als aufgespeicherte Arbeit. Dieser Gedanke beherrscht die Menschen so, daß er eigentlich einer der Grundmotoren des proletarischen Denkens der Gegenwart ist. Er ist dies insofern, als aus den nationalökonomischen Voraussetzungen, die ich Ihnen charakterisiert habe, in die Köpfe des modernen Proletariats ein scharfer Blick dafür hineingekommen ist, daß ja in der Tat, so wie die volkswirtschaftliche Ordnung, die soziale Struktur heute ist, die Arbeitskraft des Arbeiters, der ja besitzlos ist und nur seiner Hände Arbeit auf den Markt bringen kann, eine Ware ist. Ebenso wie man andere Dinge kauft, so kauft man Arbeitskraft bei dem proletarischen Arbeiter.

Gegenüber der Frage: Was bin ich eigentlich als Mensch? — empfindet der moderne Proletarier dies als etwas, was ihn am meisten bedrückt, und von wo seine Forderungen instinktiv ausgehen. Er will nicht, daß irgendein Teil von ihm verkauft wird; er kommt sich vor, man kann sagen, als ob man seine zwei Hände, seine zwei Arme ebensogut verkaufen könnte, wie man seine Arbeit kaufen und verkaufen kann. Das erscheint dem Menschen unbequem, in welcher Form das auch zum Ausdruck komme, sei es nun marxistisches Denken, oder sei es revisionistisches, oder wie man es nennen will; es liegt das Empfinden zugrunde: Andere Leute kaufen und verkaufen Waren, ich aber muß meine Arbeitskraft verkaufen.

Es wäre der Einwand nur ein Irrtum, wenn man etwa sagen würde: Auch andere Leute verkaufen ihre Arbeit. — Das ist nämlich nicht wahr. In unserer heutigen sozialen Struktur verkauft wirklich nur der proletarische Arbeiter seine Arbeit. Denn in dem Augenblick, wo man in irgendeiner Weise mit Besitzesverhältnissen verknüpft ist, hört man auf, seine Arbeitskraft zu verkaufen. Also der Bourgeois verkauft nicht seine Arbeitskraft; er kauft und verkauft Ware. Er verkauft vielleicht die Erzeugnisse seiner Arbeit; aber das ist etwas anderes, als seine Arbeit verkaufen. Über diese Dinge hat gerade der moderne Proletarier sehr scharfe Begriffe, und wer das Denken des modernen Proletariats kennt, der weiß, daß dieses Prinzip: Proletarisches Arbeiten heißt seine Arbeitskraft verkaufen - als das eigentliche treibende Element im heutigen proletarischen Denken wirkt, von den gemäßigtsten bis in die radikalsten Formen hinein. Wer das nicht ermessen kann aus den Phänomenen heraus, der versteht eben die heutige Zeit nicht, und es ist traurig, daß so viele Leute die heutige Zeit nicht verstehen. Dadurch kommen wir eben immer tiefer und tiefer in die Wirrnisse hinein, weil die Menschen nicht versuchen, ihre Zeit zu verstehen. Das ist das eine.

Das andere ist, daß sich - allerdings modifiziert durch spätere, aber in einer gewissen Weise instinktive Punkte - im Zusammenhange mit dem Charakterisierten solch ein Gedanke ausgebildet hat, wie der vom Lohngesetz. In der radikalen Form, in der dieser Gedanke früher existiert hat, existiert er allerdings im modernen proletarischen Denken nicht mehr, aber man muß doch die Form kennen, in der dieser Gedanke zum Beispiel bei Lassalle noch existiert hat; damit man sich über das orientiere, was gleichsam als ein Residuum über diesen Gedanken in der proletarischen Gegenwart noch immer existiert. Klar fixiert ist dieser Gedanke von dem sogenannten ehernen Lohngesetz vom volkswirtschaftlichen Forscher Ricardo. Aber Lassalle hat ihn noch Mitte des vorigen Jahrhunderts mit aller Energie vertreten. Er würde etwa so heißen: So wie einmal die heutige soziale Struktur ist mit der Form des Kapitals, so kann derjenige, der proletarisch arbeiten muß, niemals über ein gewisses Maximum hinaus für seine Arbeit entlohnt werden. Der Lohn muß sich immer in einer gewissen Höhe bewegen. Er kann nicht über diese Höhe steigen und nicht unter diese Höhe hinunterfallen. Die objektiven Verhältnisse selbst machen es notwendig, daß sich ein gewisser Satz von Arbeitsentlohnung geltend macht. Über den Maximal- oder meinetwillen Minimallohn - das ist ja in diesem Falle gleichgültig —- kann sich das Lohnniveau des Arbeiters nicht hinauf- und nicht herunterbewegen; wenigstens nicht wesentlich; so glaubt Ricardo, und zwar aus folgendem Grund. Er sagt: Nehmen wir an, es trete durch irgendwelche Verhältnisse, zum Beispiel durch gute Konjunktur oder irgend etwas in irgendeiner Zeit eine besondere Erhöhung des Lohnes ein. Was würde geschehen? Die Proletarier würden also plötzlich hohe Löhne bekommen, ihr Lebensstand würde sich dadurch erhöhen, sie kämen zu einem bestimmten Wohlstand. Proletarische Arbeit zu suchen wäre dann etwas, was mehr anzieht, als beim früheren Lohne. Es ist ein stärkeres Angebot von proletarischer Arbeit da, außerdem durch den Wohlstand eine stärkere Vermehrung der Arbeiter und so weiter, kurz, es ist ein stärkeres Angebot da. Die Folge davon wird sein, daß man leichter den Arbeiter bekommt. Also unterzahlt man ihn wiederum. Der Lohn fällt also wiederum zurück auf das frühere Niveau. Gerade dadurch, daß er steigt, werden Erscheinungen hervorgerufen, die ihn wieder fallen machen. Nehmen wir an, er fällt nun durch irgend etwas, so tritt eine Verelendung ein, dadurch ein geringeres Angebot. Die Arbeiter sterben früher und werden krank, haben weniger Kinder, also es tritt ein geringes Angebot an Arbeitskräften ein, und damit wird wiederum Lohnerhöhung eintreten. Man kann aber nur so weit gehen, als das eherne Niveau ist.

Natürlich haben Ricardo und auch noch Lassalle, indem sie dieses eherne Lohngesetz aufgestellt haben, an die Bestimmung des Lohnes im rein volkswirtschaftlichen Prozeß gedacht. Heute, und auch schon vor zwei, drei Jahrzehnten, sagten einem selbst schon Proletarier, wenn man ihnen in der Geschichte der Volkswirtschaftslehre das eherne Lohngesetz zitierte: Das ist nicht richtig, da haben sich Ricardo und Lassalle geirrt. Aber eigentlich ist dieser Einwand nicht richtig, denn diese Forscher konnten nur meinen, wenn die soziale Struktur sich selbst überlassen ist, dann tritt dieses eherne Lohngesetz in Kraft. Aber eben um es nicht in Kraft zu haben, wurden Arbeiterassoziationen gegründet, wurde die Staatshilfe und der Staatseinfluß zu Hilfe genommen. Die Folge davon ist, daß man den Status des Lohngesetzes künstlich erhöht. Was also darüber hinausgeht über das eherne Niveau des Lohngesetzes, das ist durch Gesetzgebung oder durch Assoziation und dergleichen hervorgerufen. Deshalb ist der Einwand nicht richtig. Sie sehen, es kommt darauf an, wie man den Gedanken wendet.

Nun, ich wollte Ihnen diese Dinge, die sich ja ins Unermeßliche vermehren ließen, nur vorführen, um Ihnen zu zeigen, wie sich im Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele die Gedanken über die Volkswirtschaft allmählich herausgebildet haben. Die Meinungen waren immer nach der einen oder nach der anderen Seite hin ausschlaggebend. Die einen meinten immer, der Volkswohlstand gedeiht am besten, wenn man die Volkswirtschaft individualistisch einrichtet, wenn man den einzelnen möglichst frei sein läßt. Die anderen meinten, dadurch werden die Schwächeren beeinträchtigt; man müsse den Schwächeren stützen dadurch, daß der Staat oder die Assoziation zu Hilfe kommt.

Ich müßte Ihnen viel charakterisieren, wenn ich all das anführen wollte, was im Laufe der Zeit zutagegetreten ist. Auf den verschiedensten Gebieten der Erde, der zivilisierten Welt, traten solche Volkswirtschaftsvorstellungen auf. Es gingen diese, die ich Ihnen charakterisiert habe, und viele andere im Grunde genommen alle darauf hinaus, nicht nur darüber nachzudenken: Wie stellt sich in der Welt, wie sie sich nun einmal bis jetzt entwickelt hat, die soziale Struktur dar? - sondern sie gingen auch darauf hinaus: Wie macht man es am besten mit dieser sozialen Struktur, damit die Menschen nicht elend leben müssen, damit die Menschen Wohlstand haben und dergleichen? Die Volkswirtschaftslehre hatte bei vielen ihrer Bearbeiter doch die Tendenz, das volkswirtschaftliche Leben zu verbessern. Utopistische und solche Naturen, wie zum Beispiel die französischen Sozialisten Saint-Simon, Auguste Comte, Louis Blanc und andere, sie haben diese Tendenz im Auge. Sie haben etwa den folgenden Gedanken: Bis jetzt hat sich mehr oder weniger die Gesellschaft, weil sie sich selbst überlassen war, so entwickelt, daß ein großer Unterschied zwischen Armen und Reichen, Wohlhabenden und Elenden zutagegetreten ist. Das muß abgeändert werden. — Sie haben zu diesem Zwecke die Gesetze der Volkswirtschaft studiert, und haben die mannigfaltigsten Gedanken hervorgebracht, um diese Dinge abzuändern und irgendwelche Besserungen herbeizuführen. Manche gingen natürlich dabei überhaupt von dem Gedanken aus, daß sich eine Art Paradies, wie ich neulich erwähnte, auf der Erde herstellen ließe.

Eine besondere Form hat aber nun dieses Denken über die soziale Struktur eben beim modernen Proletariat angenommen. Und über die Gründe, warum gerade das Proletariat prädestiniert war, solche Anschauungen auszubilden, habe ich ja hier schon gesprochen. Aber über einen besonderen Gesichtspunkt möchte ich noch ergänzende Bemerkungen machen. Gewiß, das, was Karl Marx in seinen Büchern und in denen, die er mit Friedrich Engels zusammen geschrieben hat, zum Ausdruck gebracht hat, ist ja vielfach abgeändert worden. Aber die Abänderungen sind viel geringer als die Grundimpulse, die eigentlich in diesen Dingen sind. Und man kann, trotzdem dieser Ausspruch nur sehr modifiziert gilt, im allgemeinen doch sagen: Über alle Länder der zivilisierten Erde hin, vom äußersten Westen bis nach Rußland hinüber, werden die Proletarier beherrscht, wenn auch heute nicht mehr ausgesprochen von den Konturen der marzistischen Gedanken, aber von den marxistischen Impulsen. In einer ganz eigentümlichen Weise tritt das Denken über die soziale Struktur in diesem modernen marxistischen proletarischen Denken auf.

Die Gedanken, die ich Ihnen jetzt entwickelt habe, die also auch bei den bürgerlichen Volkswirtschaftern seit dem Beginne des Bewußtseinszeitalters auftreten, sie werden aufgenommen von dem sozialistischen Denken. Sie werden aber von dem sozialistischen Denken ebenso umgeprägt, wie sie der Proletarier aus seiner proletarischen Kaste heraus nach seiner Meinung notwendig denken muß. Da tritt das Eigentümliche zutage, daß dieser Gedanke: Innerhalb der modernen kapitalistischen sozialen Struktur muß der Mensch seine Arbeitskraft als Proletarier verkaufen - theoretisch weiter ausgebildet, der treibende Motor des proletarischen Denkens wird, daß der Gedanke auftaucht: Wie ist das zu vermeiden, daß die Arbeitskraft wie eine Ware auf den Markt gebracht und verkauft werden kann? - Natürlich wirkt in diesen Impuls hinein die Anschauung, die sich auch klar formuliert bei Adam Smith und bei anderen findet, daß man es in der Ware, die man kauft, mit aufgespeicherter Arbeitskraft zu tun hat. Es ist ein ungeheuer plausibler Gedanke, ein Gedanke, der sich dann zu der Konsequenz erweitert: Ja, was läßt sich da überhaupt machen? - Wenn ich irgendeinen Rock kaufe, so ist die Arbeit, die der Schneider verwendet hat, oder derjenige, der daran beteiligt war, daß der Rock zustandegekommen ist, drinnen in dem Rocke: aufgespeicherte Arbeit. Es wird daher die Frage gar nicht so ins Auge gefaßt: Kann man die Arbeit von der Ware loslösen? — sondern das wird als etwas, ich möchte sagen, Axiomatisches, als etwas Selbstverständliches angesehen, daß unzertrennlich die Arbeit mit der Ware verbunden ist. Man sucht also nach einer sozialen Struktur, die für den Arbeiter diese unumstößliche Tatsache möglichst unschädlich machen soll, daß die Arbeit mit dem Produkte der Arbeit verbunden bleibt. Unter solchem Einflusse ist eigentlich der Marxismus entstanden, ist der Glaube entstanden, daß man nur dadurch, daß man das Produktionsmittel in die Allgemeinheit überführt, also in einer gewissen Weise die Allgemeinheit zum Besitzer der Produktionsmittel, der sämtlichen Maschinen und des Grund und Bodens und der Verkehrsmittel macht, daß man nur dadurch in einer gewissen Weise eine gerechte Entlohnung herbeiführen kann. Es entstand gar nicht die Frage: Kann man die Ware unabhängig machen von der Entlohnung? - sondern: Wie kann man eine gerechte Entlohnung herbeiführen, wenn man axiomatisch, selbstverständlich annehmen muß, daß die Arbeit in die Ware hineinfließt? — Das ist die Fragestellung, und mit der hängt alles übrige zusammen. Mit ihr hängt sogar die materialistische Auffassung der Wirtschaftslehre, die extreme materialistische Geschichtsauffassung zusammen. Die bestehen ja, wie ich Ihnen auch schon ausführte, darin, daß der moderne Proletarier denkt: Alles, was innerhalb der Menschheitskultur wirkt, alles geistige Erzeugnis, alles Denken, alle Politik, alles überhaupt, was nicht auf wirtschaftlichen Vorgängen beruht, ist nur ein Überbau, eine Ideologie, die sich auf der Grundlage desjenigen aufrichtet, was wirtschaftlich erarbeitet wird. Wirtschaft ist das Reale. Die Art, wie der Mensch in die wirtschaftliche Struktur hineingestellt ist, das ist das Reale im Menschenleben. Was er dann für Gedanken hat, das ergibt sich aus seinem wirtschaftlichen Zusammenhang. Solche Leute, die ganz stramme Marxisten sind, wie zum Beispiel Franz Mehring, die schreiben über Lessing das ist nur ein Beispiel -, indem sie untersuchen: Wie war das Wirtschaftsleben in der zweiten Hälfte des achtzehnten Jahrhunderts? Wie hat man da fabriziert, wie hat man eingekauft? Wie war das Verhältnis vom Gewerbe zu der übrigen Menschheit? Wie hat man infolgedessen gedacht? Wie ist Lessing zustandegekommen? — Diese besondere Persönlichkeit mit ihren Leistungen, Lessing, wird aus dem Wirtschaftsleben der zweiten Hälfte des achtzehnten Jahrhunderts heraus erklärt! Kautsky oder andere versuchen sogar, das Auftreten des Christentums von diesem Gesichtspunkte aus zu erklären. Sie untersuchen die wirtschaftlichen Verhältnisse am Beginne unserer Zeitrechnung und stellen fest: Es walteten die und die Produktionsverhältnisse. Das bedingt, daß man damals in einer gewissen Weise das, was sie eine Art kommunistischen Denkens nennen, entfaltete, das dann auf den Namen des Christus Jesus getauft worden ist. Die Wirklichkeit im Beginne unserer Zeitrechnung ist in Wahrheit die wirtschaftliche Ordnung. Das Christentum ist eine Ideologie, ein Überbau, gleichsam ein Spiegelbild unserer wirtschaftlichen Ordnung. Es gibt nichts anderes als wirtschaftliche Ordnung. Das andere ist alles darüber schwebend, Fata Morgana, Spiegelbild, nichts Wirkliches, höchstens etwas, was — wie ich schon in früheren Vorträgen charakterisiert habe — wieder zurückwirkt auf die wirtschaftlichen Verhältnisse, aber in geringem Maße auf dem Umwege durch menschliche Vorgänge anderer Art.

Diese zwei Dinge wirken zusammen. Die Entrüstung darüber, daß der Mensch einen Teil von sich, seine Arbeitskraft, wie eine Ware behandeln lassen muß: das wirkt zusammen mit der vollständig ins Extreme getriebenen materialistischen Vorstellung, daß das wirtschaftliche Leben das einzige ist, was wirklich ist.

Natürlich haben nicht alle Menschen sich dieser Anschauung zugewendet, obwohl Millionen von Menschen, gerade die Proletarier, von diesen Anschauungen mehr oder weniger beherrscht sind. Aber bei den andern Menschen wurde ja mit Bezug auf diese Dinge eine andere Sache üblich. Bei den anderen Menschen ist das ja nicht üblich, was bei den Proletariern üblich ist. Wenn die Proletarier ihre acht oder zehn oder manchmal mehr Stunden gearbeitet haben, dann finden sie sich abends zusammen und besprechen diese Frage, lassen sich diese Frage vortragen; auch Frauenversammlungen finden da statt. Sie kümmern sich, jeder einzelne, um die Beschaffenheit der sozialen Struktur und denken in ihrer Art darüber nach, lassen sich die Ergebnisse derjenigen, die über diese Dinge nachdenken, mitteilen und so weiter. Sie wissen Bescheid, nach ihrer Art allerdings, aber sie wissen Bescheid. — In der darüber liegenden Schichte, die man die Bourgeoisie nennt — Sie werden das zugeben müssen -, ist das nicht der Fall, und nach «getaner Arbeit», das sagen wir in Gänsefüßchen, beschäftigt man sich mit anderem. Mit den Proletariern beschäftigt man sich höchstens in der Weise — und man glaubt dann schon sehr viel getan zu haben -, daß man es sich auf der Bühne vorspielen läßt, von irgendeinem Spießer als Dichter zubereitet. Aber die Gedanken über die wirtschaftliche Ordnung, die läßt man die Professoren an den Universitäten denken. Die sind ja dazu angestellt, die machen das schon. Autoritätsgläubig ist man ja allerdings nicht, aber man schwört auf dasjenige, was diese Professoren an den Universitäten über solche Dinge ausgedacht haben; das muß selbstverständlich richtig sein, denn sie werden vom Staate bezahlt und sind überhaupt die Leute, die dazu da sind. Ja, aber sehen Sie, unter diesen Professoren hat sich allmählich eine merkwürdige Volkswirtschaftslehre herausgebildet. Wenn sie heute Bücher schreiben, so nennen sie das die «historische Schule ». Sie handeln ab den Merkantilisten, den Physiokraten, Adam Smith, den Sozialismus, den Anarchismus und so weiter, und dann ihre eigene Anschauung; das ist die «historische Schule». Sie fragen sich: Wie soll man denn zu dem Gedanken kommen, wie man es machen soll? — Wahrhaftig, hilflos sind diese Menschen in dieser Beziehung. Sie raffen sich nicht zu einer solchen Aktivität des Denkens auf, die nach Vorstellungen drängt, wie man es machen soll, um irgendeine gesellschaftliche Struktur herbeizuführen. Solche Spießbürger wie, sagen wir, Lujo Brentano oder wie Schmoller oder wie Roscher, die kommen gar nicht darauf, das Denken in Aktivität zu versetzen, sondern sie meinen, man muß die Erscheinungen studieren, wie es der Naturforscher auch macht. Ein solcher Mensch läßt die Erscheinungen ablaufen und studiert sie. Er studiert einfach die geschichtliche Entwickelung der Menschheit, vielleicht noch die geschichtliche Entwickelung der Vorstellungen der Menschen über ihre Wirtschaft. Das, was da ist, das beschreibt man. Man macht es höchstens so wie Lujo Brentano: Wenn man es nicht gerade in seiner Heimat beobachten will, reist man in ein Land mit repräsentativer Wirtschaft, nach England, macht da Untersuchungen, beschreibt dann, wie dort die Verhältnisse von Arbeitnehmer und Arbeitgeber sind und dergleichen. Man lernt erkennen, daß da reiche Leute sind, wie Kredit erworben wird, wie das Kapital arbeitet, daß Elend da ist, daß Besitzlose da sind, daß manche nichts zu essen haben, mehr oder weniger durch diese oder jene Umstände nichts zu essen haben. Aber dann sagen die Menschen: Ja, die Wissenschaft hat nicht die Aufgabe, zu zeigen, wie sich die Dinge entwickeln sollen, sondern nur hinzuweisen, wie sie sich entwickeln. Aber was wird nun schon schließlich aus einer solchen Wissenschaft, die doch auf das praktische Leben geht, wenn sie eigentlich nur beobachtet, wie die Dinge sich entwickeln? Es ist schon so, wie wenn ich einen Maler heranbilden will und ihm sage: Versuche vor allen Dingen zu allen möglichen Malern zu gehen und beobachte, wie es der eine gut, der andere schlecht macht und so weiter, aber selber mache nichts! - Nicht wahr, auf einem solchen Gebiete wird die Sache gleich paradox; aber es ist wirklich mit dem andern zu vergleichen. Es ist nämlich schon zum Aus-der-Haut-Fahren - verzeihen Sie den Ausdruck -, wenn man wirklich in eine Betrachtung dessen eintritt, was heute, man kann nicht sagen geleistet, sondern vertrottelt wird, wenn naturwissenschaftliche Methode auf solche Dinge wie Volkswirtschaft oder ähnliches eingehen will. Denn es kommt dabei gar nichts heraus, weil im Grunde genommen schon die Voraussetzungen die allertörichtesten sind. Höchstens, nicht wahr, daß dann sich aus dieser Schar die sogenannten Katheder-Sozialisten herausbilden, die eben aus ihrer Betrachtung dessen, was vorhanden ist, zu dem Schlusse kommen: Es muß etwas geschehen. - Und dann macht man Gesetze, die dem oder jenem abhelfen sollen.

Aber gerade diese Hilflosigkeit hat ja mitgewirkt zur Herbeiführung dieser Situation. Und es würde heute eine Feigheit sein, nicht darauf hinzuweisen, daß dasjenige, was die heutige, natürlich keine Autorität anbetende Menschheit sich vorsagen läßt auf diesem Gebiete, womit sie sich befriedigt erklärt, vielfach schuld ist an dem Chaos, in das wir hineingekommen sind. Diese Dinge sind so ernst, daß man sie wirklich auch in ihrer wahren Gestalt anfassen muß. Dann entsteht schon die Frage: Was wirkt noch tiefer in all diesen Dingen? Warum ist das alles so gekommen? Warum wirken solche schwankenden Vorstellungen auf einem der Menschheit wichtigsten Gebiete, wie ich Ihnen auseinandergesetzt habe?

Betrachten wir eine solche Vorstellung, wie sie zwar illusionär, aber außerordentlich wirksam ist, betrachten wir die — meinetwillen modifizierte marxistische Vorstellung, die im wesentlichen ja die Vorstellung der heutigen Professorenköpfe ist: Wirklich ist nur die Wirtschaft, wirklich ist nur die ökonomische Struktur; das andere ist alles ideologisch, Überbau, Fata Morgana, die sich darum herumentwickelt. Etwas höchst Merkwürdiges im Grunde: der absolute Unglaube an alles, was der Mensch als Geistiges produzieren kann aus all den Vorstellungen, die sich seit dem Heraufkommen des Zeitalters der Bewußtseinsseele entwickeln. Da macht sich das geltend, daß die Menschen immer mehr zu dem hingedrängt werden, was äußerlich bekannt ist, was äußerlich handgreiflich für die Sinne da ist. Das andere fliehen sie, meiden sie. Und unter diesem Fliehen, unter diesem Meiden haben sich nicht nur die sozialen Gedanken, sondern die sozialen Empfindungen und schließlich die sozialen Ereignisse in unserer Zeit herausgebildet, und werden sich weiter herausbilden, wenn nicht der Ruf nach einem wirklich geisteswissenschaftlichen Durchdringen dieser Tatsache gehört wird.

Was liegt da zugrunde? Das liegt zugrunde, daß wir eben in das Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele eingetreten sind, daß wir seit dem fünfzehnten Jahrhundert darinnen sind, und daß diese Entwickelung innerhalb des Zeitalters der Bewußtseinsseele, dieses Hindrängen des Menschen nach der Erweckung der Bewußtseinsseele notwendig macht, daß sich der Mensch immer mehr und mehr einem Punkt seiner Entwickelung nähert, wo er eigentlich — aus «Kontra-Instinkten » heraus - fliehen will. Ein Wesentliches wird darinnen bestehen, daß der moderne Mensch diesen Fluchtinstinkt überwindet; er will fliehen vor etwas, in das er doch hinein muß. Ich habe Ihnen neulich, als ich das letztemal hier gesprochen habe, gesagt: Über die verschiedenen nationalen Gebiete hin, den Westen, die mittleren Länder, den Osten, ist differenziert auch die Art, wie der Mensch an den Hüter der Schwelle herankommt, wenn er die geistige Welt betritt. Ein SichHinbewegen zum Erleben solcher Erlebnisse, wie sie bewußt beim Hüter der Schwelle gemacht werden können, wie sie aber instinktiv mehr oder weniger von den Menschen nach und nach im Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele gemacht werden müssen - ein Hingedrängtwerden zu den Erfahrungen beim Hüter der Schwelle in einer bestimmten, wenn auch äußerlichen Form, das ist es, was wie ein Impuls, wie ein Instinkt, wie ein Trieb in den modernen Menschen wirkt, und was sie fliehen. Sie fürchten sich, dahin zu kommen, wohin sie eigentlich kommen sollten.

Das ist sehr gesetzmäßig in der modernen Entwickelung des Menschen. Nehmen Sie das, was ich vorhin als äußerliche Charakteristik des modernen Strebens vorgeführt habe. Der Mensch strebt danach, zu erkennen, was er ist als Mensch, was er wert ist als Mensch, welche Kraft er hat, was seine Würde ist als Mensch. Der Mensch strebt danach, sich als Menschen selber anzuschauen, endlich zu einem Bilde seines eigenen Wesens zu kommen. Man kann nicht zu einem Bilde des Menschen kommen, wenn man innerhalb der Sinneswelt stehenbleiben will, denn der Mensch erschöpft sich nicht in der Sinneswelt, der Mensch ist nicht bloß ein sinnliches Wesen. In den Zeitaltern der instinktiven Entwickelung, wo man nicht nach einem Bilde des Menschen oder nach der Menschenwürde oder nach der Menschenkraft fragt, da kann man vorbeigehen an der Tatsache, daß, wenn man den Menschen erkennen will, man aus der Sinneswelt hinausgehen und in die geistige Welt hineinsehen muß, daß man mit der übersinnlichen Welt wenigstens in irgendeiner Form intellektuell in unserem Zeitalter des Bewußtseins Bekanntschaft machen muß. Da wirkt aber dann unbewußt dasselbe, was bewußt der zu Initiierende zu überwinden hat. Unbewußt wirkt zunächst noch in unseren Zeitgenossen und in den Menschen, deren soziale Gedanken ich Ihnen geschildert habe, diese Furcht vor dem Unbekannten, das betrachtet werden muß. Furcht, Mutlosigkeit, Feigheit, das ist es, wovon die moderne Menschheit beherrscht ist. Und wenn diese moderne Menschheit sagt: Wirtschaft ist das Handgreifliche, was alles bewirkt — so ist diese Anschauung dadurch entstanden, daß man sich fürchtet vor dem, was unsichtbar ist, was nicht handgreiflich ist. Dem will man sich nicht nähern, das will man vermeiden, das biegt man zur Ideologie, zur Fata Morgana um. Und man biegt es deshalb zur Ideologie, zur Fata Morgana um, weil man sich davor fürchtet. Ein Furcht-, ein Angstpunkt ist die moderne soziale Weltanschauung in bezug auf diejenigen Punkte, die ich Ihnen charakterisiert habe. Mögen manche Menschen, die sich innerhalb des Strebens dieser modernen sozialen Weltanschauung äußerlich noch so mutvoll zeigen, auf der einen Seite noch so couragiert sein — vor dem Spirituellen, das ihnen entgegentreten muß in irgendeiner Form, worin sie den Menschen kennenlernen wollen, vor dem haben sie Furcht, vor dem treten sie feig zurück. Ein Furchtprodukt, ein Angstprodukt, das ist es, was in den modernen sozialistischen Weltanschauungen zutage tritt.

Von diesem Gesichtspunkte aus müssen die Dinge ins Auge gefaßt werden. Denn der moderne Mensch muß dreierlei Dinge kennenlernen, weil er naturgemäß zu diesen dreierlei Dingen geführt wird, differenziert nach Westen, Mitte und Osten, so wie ich es Ihnen das letztemal charakterisiert habe. Aber er wird naturgemäß in irgendeiner Form zu diesen dreierlei Dingen geführt. Wenn es auch nur der Initiierte sieht, was an diesen drei Punkten vorhanden ist, fühlen, empfinden, in seinen Intellekt aufnehmen — wenn auch nicht in sein Sehvermögen - muß es nach und nach jeder moderne Mensch, wenn er die wirtschaftliche Struktur durchdringen will. Erstens muß der moderne Mensch eine deutliche Empfindung oder wenigstens eine deutliche intellektuelle Vorstellung bekommen von den Kräften, die im Weltenall die Niedergangskräfte, die zerstörenden Kräfte sind. Unter den Kräften, die man gern verfolgt - und man täuscht sich deshalb, weil man sie nur mit den Sympathien des Gernhabens verfolgt -, sind eben die aufbauenden Kräfte. Man will immer aufbauen, aufbauen, aufbauen. Aber in der Welt ist nicht nur Evolution oder Aufbau, es ist auch Involution oder Abbau vorhanden. Wir selber tragen den Abbau in uns. Unser entwickeltes Nervensystem, Gehirnsystem, ist in fortwährendem Abbau begriffen. Abbau ist in der Welt. Mit diesen Kräften des Abbaus muß der Mensch bekannt werden. Vorurteilslos und unbefangen muß er sich sagen: Gerade auf dem Wege, der sich in dem Zeitalter entwickelt, in dem die Bewußtseinsseele voll erwachen soll, sind am wirksamsten die Abbaukräfte. Sie konzentrieren sich manchmal, sie konsolidieren sich, diese Abbaukräfte, und dann entwickelt sich so etwas wie diese letzten viereinhalb Jahre. Da zeigt sich der Menschheit in konzentriertem Zustande etwas, was auch sonst immer vorhanden ist. Aber das muß nicht unbewußt und instinktiv bleiben, das muß gerade in diesem Zeitalter voll bekannt werden. Die Abbaukräfte, die Todeskräfte, die lähmenden Kräfte — der Mensch wendet gern sein Antlitz von ihnen ab; dadurch aber macht er sich blind und lernt nicht mitarbeiten an der Evolution, weil er die Abbaukräfte flieht.

Das zweite, mit dem der Mensch sich bekanntmachen muß und was er wiederum flieht, das ist, daß der Mensch in diesem Zeitalter der intellektuellen Entwickelung, das heißt der Entwickelung im Zeitalter der Bewußtseinsseele, unbedingt dahin kommen muß, sich gewissermaßen einen neuen Schwerpunkt seines Wesens zu suchen. Die instinktive Entwickelung hat ihm, auch in Gedanken, einen Schwerpunkt gegeben. Er glaubt festzustehen auf seinen Anschauungen, auf seinen Vorstellungen, die ihm eben durch Blut oder Abstammung oder sonstwie zukommen. Das kann der Mensch fortan nicht. Der Mensch muß sich loslösen von dem, worauf er feststand, was sich instinktiv ausgebildet hat. Der Mensch muß sich gewissermaßen an den Abgrund stellen, muß unter sich die Leere, den Abgrund fühlen, weil er in sich den Mittelpunkt seines Wesens finden muß. Davor scheut der Mensch zurück, davor hat er Furcht.

Und das dritte ist: Der Mensch muß in voller Gewalt kennenlernen, wenn er sich gegen die Zukunft hin entwickelt, den Impuls der Selbstsucht, des Egoismus. Unser Zeitalter ist dazu angetan, dem Menschen klarzumachen, wie er, wenn er sich seiner Natur überläßt, ein egoistisches Wesen ist. Man muß erst alle Quellen des Egoismus in der menschlichen Natur erforschen, um den Egoismus zu überwinden. Liebe tritt erst auf als das Gegenstück zur Selbstliebe. Man muß über den Abgrund der Selbstliebe hinüberkommen, wenn man dasjenige kennenlernen will, was als soziale Wärme die soziale Struktur der Gegenwart und der Zukunft durchdringen soll, namentlich wenn man es nicht bloß in der Theorie, sondern in voller Praxis kennenlernen will. -— Sich dieser Empfindung zu nähern, die der zu Initiierende beim Hüter der Schwelle beim Eintritt in die übersinnliche Welt klar schaut, das erfüllt die Menschen wiederum mit Furcht, indem ihnen klar wird: Anders läßt sich nicht eintreten in das Zeitalter, das notwendig eine soziale Struktur hervorbringen muß, als durch Liebe, die nicht Selbstliebe ist, die Liebe für den andern Menschen, Interesse an andern Menschen ist. Das empfinden die Menschen wie etwas Brennendes, wie etwas, was sie verzehrt, wie etwas, was ihnen ihr eigenes Wesen nimmt, indem es ihnen die Selbstliebe, das Recht zur Selbstliebe nimmt. Und so wie sie das Übersinnliche fliehen, vor dem sie Furcht haben, weil es ihnen ein Unbekanntes ist, so fliehen sie die Liebe, weil sie ihnen ein brennendes Feuer ist. Und wie die Menschen in dem Zeitalter, in dem man vorbereiten muß die spirituellen Impulse, sich gerade die Augen verbinden, die Ohren zustopfen vor der Wahrheit des Übersinnlichen, indem sie zum Beispiel im Marxismus und im proletarisch verführten Denken von heute darauf hinweisen, daß man sich auf das Handgreifliche stützen müsse, um gerade abzulenken von dem Übersinnlichen, wie sie das Gegenteil von dem verfolgen, was auf diesem Gebiete in der wirklichen Tendenz der Menschheitsentwickelung liegt, so machen sie es auch auf dem Gebiete der Liebe. Sogar in den ’Tendenzworten prägt sich das aus. Man stellt Ideale auf, die das Gegenteil von dem sind, was eigentlich in der Menschheitsentwickelung liegt und angestrebt werden muß.

Als die erste, bedeutendste Kundgebung für die moderne proletatische Lebensauffassung, das «Kommunistische Manifest», 1848 erschien, da war dieses «Kommunistische Manifest» des Karl Marx bereits ausgestattet mit den Worten, die jetzt fast auf jedem sozialistischen Buch und auf jeder sozialistischen Broschüre als Motto zu finden sind: «Proletarier aller Länder, vereinigt euch!»

Wenn man nur ein wenig Sinn hat für eine Wirklichkeitsauffassung, dann muß man über diese Worte zu einem präzisen, aber sonderbaren paradoxen Urteil kommen. Was heißt das: «Proletarier aller Länder, vereinigt euch!»? Das heißt: Wirket zusammen, wirket miteinander, seid einander Brüder, seid Genossen! — Das ist Liebe! — Lasset die Liebe unter euch wirken! — Es tritt die Tendenz tumultuarisch auf, aber wie?: — Proletarier, werdet euch bewußt, daß ihr herausgesondert seid aus der Menschheit, hasset die anderen, die nicht Proletarier sind, lasset den Haß den Impuls eurer Vereinigung sein! - In einer sonderbaren Weise sind zusammengekoppelt Liebe und Haß, die Vereinigung wird angestrebt aus dem Haß heraus, dem Gegensatz der Vereinigung! Bemerkt wird es nur nicht, weil man heute weit entfernt davon ist, seine Gedanken mit der Wirklichkeit zu verknüpfen. Aber es ist der Furchtgedanke vor der Liebe, die zwar angeschlagen, aber zu gleicher Zeit gemieden wird, weil man vor ihr zurückschreckt, zurückbebt wie vor einem verzehrenden Feuer, indem man gerade solche Worte heraushebt und zum Motto macht in der sozialen Bewegung.

So kann nur das geisteswissenschaftliche Durchdrungensein dessen, was wirklich ist, Aufschluß geben für das, was in der Gegenwart wirkt, und das man kennen muß, damit man sich wirklich bewußt hineinstellen kann in diese Gegenwart. Es ist nicht so einfach, dasjenige, was heute in der Menschheit pulst, zu verfolgen. Geisteswissenschaft ist notwendig zu diesem Verfolgen. Das sollte nicht außer acht gelassen werden. Und der allein steht richtig in dieser geisteswissenschaftlichen Bewegung, der ernst genug auch diese Dinge zu nehmen versteht.

Eighth Lecture

From the various considerations we have made recently about the social impulses of recent times, the present, and the near future, you will have seen that in the various phenomena that have emerged from these impulses, a kind of fundamental tendency is asserting itself, albeit a fundamental tendency that initially characterizes the course of events in a very superficial way. We can say: Certainly, the most diverse phenomena are occurring, the most diverse demands are being made; social and anti-social worldviews are emerging. This or that is being done out of such social and anti-social worldviews. But if we want to summarize from the point of view we have now gained, we can ask ourselves: What actually lies at the root of this, what is working its way to the surface of human destiny and human development? Then, at least outwardly, we can characterize the matter as follows: Human beings also want a social order; they want to give social coexistence a social structure within which they can become conscious, in a manner appropriate to our age of the consciousness soul, of what they can know as human beings in their dignity, in their significance, and in their power. They want to find themselves as human beings in this social order. The impulses that were once instinctive guided human beings to do this or that, to think this or that, to feel this or that. These instinctive impulses want to transform themselves into conscious impulses. In the age of the consciousness soul, which began in the fifteenth century and will last until the fourth millennium, human beings will only be able to bring these conscious impulses properly into their lives if they become increasingly aware in this age of what they are as human beings and what they are capable of as human beings within the social structure in which they live socially, politically, or in other ways.

I have already indicated that what can only be correctly and clearly understood in the sense of this age of consciousness can emerge in a more or less tumultuous manner here and there, both in the views and thoughts of human beings and in the events in which human beings live in the present. It is quite characteristic, I would say shockingly characteristic, of what is expressed in a speech given by Trotsky. If you take what I have just said about placing the will, the human being, at the center of the worldview, you will hear words such as those spoken by Trotsky as something shocking. He says: “The communist doctrine, or socialist doctrine, has set itself as one of its most important tasks to achieve a situation on our old sinful earth in which people will stop shooting at each other. One of the tasks of socialism or communism is to create an order in which man will be worthy of his name for the first time.” We are accustomed to saying that the word “human being” sounds proud. Gorky said: “Human being, that sounds proud.” But in reality, when one looks back on these three and three-quarter years of bloody murder, one wants to cry out: “Human being, that sounds shameful!”

In any case, you see this question tumultuously raised here: How can man become conscious of his humanity, his human value, and his human power, as it were? Right at the beginning of a programmatic speech, it is placed at the center of consideration. And so, if you look more closely, you will encounter many people with the same appearance. One can only understand this phenomenon—I mean the way in which what is clearly understood through spiritual science haunts the mind in an unclear form—one can only understand this haunting, this phenomenon, if one also considers various things that we have not yet examined in relation to the social thinking of the fifth post-Atlantean epoch. Actually, an enormous amount has changed, and with a certain leap, since the time when this fifth post-Atlantean period began in the fifteenth post-Christian century, following the fourth, which ended at that time — which, as you know, began in the eighth pre-Christian century. People simply do not notice how radically the spiritual constitution of civilized humanity has changed during the transition from, for example, the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries to the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. I have pointed out to you many phenomena in the artistic realm, in the realm of thought, and in other realms from which you can see this change. Today we want to consider something else that is particularly significant for the forces at work in the present and the near future. Actually, one can say that public economic life, public national economic life as it is integrated into the social structure, has only been observed in a conscious way since the beginning of the fifth post-Atlantean period. Before that, what people think about today emerged more or less instinctively. It was not until around the sixteenth century that people began to consciously ask the question: What is the economic order? What is the best economic order? What laws underlie the economic order? And it is from these considerations that the impulses of the socialist worldview have developed to this day. In the past, these things were more or less instinctively organized, from person to person, from association to association, from guild to guild, from corporation to corporation, or even from empire to empire. It was only with the emergence of the modern state, which dates back to around the sixteenth century, that we began to think about economic issues.

Now, when you look at something like this, you must not lose sight of the following. You must be clear about this: as long as something acts instinctively, it acts with a certain degree of certainty. Call it “divine order,” call it “natural order,” whatever you like, instincts are something that act with a certain degree of certainty throughout human development, something that cannot be shaken by thought, or rather, something that is not shaken by thought. And uncertainty only begins when the same objects, in whose domains the certainty of instincts previously operated, are now penetrated by human reflection, by the human intellect. And only gradually does man—one might say, after having gone through the most varied errors—consciously gain the certainty that he previously had for other circumstances through instinct.

Of course, one must not object: So let us return to instinct. Conditions have changed, and under the changed conditions, instinct would no longer be the right thing. Moreover, humanity is in a state of development and is passing from instinct to conscious life in relation to these things. The demand that we should return to the old instincts would be about as sensible as someone who is fifty years old suddenly deciding to become twenty again. Here we see how economic thinking began around the sixteenth century and in the sixteenth century. Conscious attention is directed toward phenomena that were previously experienced instinctively within the context of human society.

It is interesting to consider at least some of the ideas and concepts that people have formed about the social order. For example, the so-called mercantilists were the first to emerge with certain ideas about economic and social life. Their ideas are actually entirely dependent on the legal concepts that had previously been formed in legal or other contexts in public life, and they use these ideas to try to understand the course and development of trade and the burgeoning industry. The ideas of the mercantilists depend above all on their view of trade and industry. But they were also influenced by other things, such as the fact that the modern, more absolutist monarchy with its entourage, the civil service, had taken on its distinctive character at that time. These ideas were conditioned by the fact that the discovery of America had brought a lot of precious metals into Europe and that the old economy had been replaced by a money economy. Such factors influenced the ideas of the first teachers of economics, the mercantilists. According to the ideas they had formed, these people believed it was important to think of the public economy, public social coexistence, according to the model of the old private economy. And for the old private economy, one had the old Roman legal ideas. As I said, these were continued, and attempts were simply made to extend the laws of the private economy into public life.

These ideas produced a peculiar result, and it is not uninteresting to trace what people gradually focused their attention on in their thinking. They produced the result that the mercantilists said to themselves: The essence of a national economy, of a national community, is based on having as much equivalent as possible for the goods to be traded and produced by industry within a national economic territory. In other words, it was important to people to devise a social structure that would bring as much money as possible into the country they had in mind. They saw the prosperity of that country in the money that was available. And how, they thought, could the prosperity of that country, in which the prosperity of the individual would then also be the greatest conceivable, be increased? By creating an internal structure for the country that allows as much money as possible to circulate within the country and as little money as possible to flow out of the country to other countries, so that as much money as possible is concentrated within the country.

This view was then challenged by another view, known as the physiocratic view. This view was based on the idea that The amount of money held in a country is not actually important in terms of prosperity; what matters is how much is extracted from the soil through labor, how much is gained in goods through the exploitation of natural forces. The circulation of goods in trade and the accumulation of money essentially achieve only something illusory. It does not really increase prosperity.

You can see two completely different points of view on the economy in these two successive views. I would ask you to focus your attention on this. For it would be very easy to believe that, once you have learned it, it is extremely easy to say what determines prosperity and what is the best type of economy. When you see that people who think about these things, who even make thinking about them their profession, come to opposite conclusions over time, you will no longer say that it is such an easy thing to think about these things.

Because the physiocrats placed the main value on the production of goods through the cultivation of the soil, of nature in general, they came to the conclusion that people should actually be left to their own devices so that they would be driven by free competition to extract as much as possible from the natural basis of existence. While the mercantilists were more interested in imposing customs duties and closing countries off from the outside world so that the outflow of money would not be too great and the prosperity of the people would be increased by keeping money in the country, the physiocrats came to the opposite view that it is precisely when one imports and exports freely from one country to another that the power to exploit the soil is increased throughout the world, and with it the prosperity of each individual country. You see, right at the dawn of conscious thinking about economic matters, opposing ideas emerged in a wide variety of directions.

We can then follow how an influential view took hold in the field of economics, which actually had an enormous impact on legislation, but also on the ideas that economists had about these matters. This is the view of Adam Smith, who asked himself the question: How can a social structure be brought about that is suitable for shaping the prosperity of the individual and the prosperity of the whole in the best possible way? Adam Smith actually came to the view—and we would like to point out a characteristic point here—that the completely individual organization of the economy was the very best thing. He assumed that goods, commodities, which ultimately constitute the content of the national economy and which are to be bought and sold, are actually the result of human labor. One could say that his view was this: when you buy something, it has come into being through human labor. So, in a sense, goods are crystallized human labor. And he believed that prosperity is best achieved precisely because of this basis of the national economy, by not preventing people from producing freely through legislation. The individual will achieve the best for the whole when he achieves the best for himself. Adam Smith is roughly of the opinion that one also achieves the best for the whole of humanity when one achieves the best for oneself. One can then best give up things and achieve the best for humanity when one achieves the best for oneself. It is best for the individual and for humanity when the national economy is organized individualistically, when no special restrictions and the like are imposed by legislation.

Now you see, the whole direction of thought of such economists is toward the question: How can the social structure best be organized? — But now you may ask yourself a question that you might consider the most important one, one that, in its peculiarity, is not entirely clear even to the physiocrats. The economic systems I have discussed so far consider how best to bring about the economic structure. But pursuing these ideas that emerge here always reminds us that there is also the other question: What does the entire economy actually want? It does not want to, or at least cannot, merely distribute what is there; it must also ensure that there is something there, that material goods are actually produced. It is also important to extract goods from the earth. What is the relationship between humans and the goods extracted from the earth? Malthus was actually the first to consciously think about this, and his thoughts followed a line of reasoning that, when you get right down to it, can make people a bit uneasy. It's not totally unfounded, what Malthus brought to light as a key question and as a view on this key question. He said: If one looks at the increase in the earth's population – he was of the opinion, as are many modern people, that the earth's population is constantly increasing – and if one looks at the increase in the amount of food produced, then a relationship becomes apparent. Malthus expresses this somewhat mathematically by saying that the increase in food proceeds in arithmetic progression, while the increase in the number of people proceeds in geometric progression. I can perhaps clarify this with a few figures. Let us assume that the ratio of food increase is 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, then we would have the geometric ratio: 1, 2, 4, 8, 16. In other words, he means that the population is growing much faster than food production. He therefore believes that the development of humanity cannot escape the danger of a struggle for existence and that there will eventually be far too many people in relation to the increase in food. He therefore views the economic development of humanity from a completely different perspective, namely from the perspective of the relationship between humans and the conditions on Earth. He concludes, or at least his followers do, that providing extensive care for the poor and similar measures actually run counter to development, as this only breeds overpopulation, which is harmful to the development of humanity. He even goes so far as to say that those who are weak in life should be left without support, because it is important that the inadequate be eliminated from life. He then tries other means, which I will not discuss here, but can only hint at. He seeks to recommend the two-child system in particular in order to curb nature's tendency toward overpopulation. He regards wars as something that must necessarily occur in human development because of the natural tendency for population growth to far outpace the growth of food supplies.

You see, a rather pessimistic view of the economic development of humanity enters the story here. It cannot be said that this question: How is man connected to the natural basis of his economy? — has received much attention in recent times. People in recent times have not even been clearly aware that research should be conducted in this direction. Then, attention was repeatedly drawn to the social structure itself, to the way in which people distribute what is available in order to achieve the greatest possible prosperity; the question was not how to extract as much as possible from the earth, but rather how to distribute it.

Now, in the course of these thoughts, various things arise that are important to note because they prepare the social and socialist thinking of the present, which has already led people to a high degree and will lead them even further into a kind of social chaos from which the right way out must necessarily be sought. I have already hinted at one thing, namely that Adam Smith, for example, clearly expresses the idea that what one buys as a good, the commodity, is stored labor. And in a sense, the idea emerges as something that corresponds to a natural necessity: one cannot regard what appears as a commodity as anything other than stored labor. This idea dominates people to such an extent that it is actually one of the fundamental driving forces of contemporary proletarian thinking. It is so inasmuch as the economic conditions I have characterized have given the modern proletariat a keen insight into the fact that, given the economic order and social structure of today, the labor power of the worker, who is destitute and can offer only the labor of his hands on the market, is indeed a commodity. Just as one buys other things, one buys labor power from the proletarian worker.

When faced with the question: What am I actually as a human being? — the modern proletarian feels that this is something that oppresses him most, and from which his demands instinctively arise. He does not want any part of himself to be sold; he feels, one might say, that his two hands, his two arms, could just as well be sold as his labor can be bought and sold. This seems inconvenient to people, whatever form it takes, whether it be Marxist thinking, revisionist thinking, or whatever you want to call it; the underlying feeling is that other people buy and sell goods, but I have to sell my labor power.

It would only be a mistake to object by saying that other people also sell their labor. That is not true. In our present social structure, only the proletarian worker really sells his labor. For the moment one is connected in any way with property relations, one ceases to sell one's labor power. The bourgeois does not sell his labor power; he buys and sells commodities. He may sell the products of his labor, but that is something different from selling his labor. The modern proletarian has very clear ideas about these things, and anyone who is familiar with the thinking of the modern proletariat knows that this principle—that proletarian labor means selling one's labor power—is the real driving force in contemporary proletarian thinking, from its most moderate to its most radical forms. Anyone who cannot grasp this from the phenomena does not understand the present age, and it is sad that so many people do not understand the present age. This is precisely why we are sinking deeper and deeper into confusion, because people do not try to understand their times. That is one thing.

The other thing is that, in connection with what has been characterized, a thought such as that of the law of wages has developed, albeit modified by later, but in a certain sense instinctive, points. In the radical form in which this idea existed in the past, it no longer exists in modern proletarian thinking, but one must nevertheless be familiar with the form in which this idea still existed, for example, in Lassalle, in order to orient oneself to what still exists, as it were, as a residue of this idea in the proletarian present. This idea is clearly defined by the so-called iron law of wages formulated by the economist Ricardo. But Lassalle still defended it with all his energy in the middle of the last century. It would be expressed something like this: Just as the present social structure is determined by the form of capital, so those who are forced to work as proletarians can never be paid more than a certain maximum for their labor. Wages must always remain at a certain level. They cannot rise above this level or fall below it. The objective conditions themselves make it necessary that a certain rate of remuneration for labor be enforced. Above the maximum or, for that matter, the minimum wage—which is irrelevant in this case—the wage level of the worker cannot rise or fall, at least not significantly. This is what Ricardo believes, and for the following reason. He says: Let us assume that, due to some circumstances, for example a good economic situation or something else at some point in time, there is a special increase in wages. What would happen? The proletarians would suddenly receive high wages, their standard of living would rise, and they would achieve a certain level of prosperity. Seeking proletarian work would then be more attractive than it was at the previous wage level. There is a greater supply of proletarian labor, and, moreover, the prosperity leads to a greater increase in the number of workers, and so on; in short, there is a greater supply. The result will be that it will be easier to find workers. So they are underpaid again. Wages thus fall back to their previous level. Precisely because it rises, phenomena are brought about which cause it to fall again. Let us assume that it now falls due to some cause, so that impoverishment sets in, resulting in a lower supply. Workers die earlier and become ill, have fewer children, so there is a low supply of labor, and this in turn leads to wage increases. However, one can only go as far as the iron level.

Of course, Ricardo and Lassalle, in establishing this iron law of wages, were thinking of the determination of wages in a purely economic process. Today, and even two or three decades ago, even proletarians themselves would say, when you quoted the iron law of wages from the history of economic theory: That is not correct; Ricardo and Lassalle were mistaken. But this objection is not really correct, because these researchers could only mean that if the social structure is left to its own devices, then this iron law of wages comes into effect. But it was precisely in order to prevent it from coming into effect that workers' associations were founded and state aid and state influence were called upon. The result of this is that the status of the wage law is artificially raised. Anything that goes beyond the iron level of the wage law is brought about by legislation or by association and the like. Therefore, the objection is not correct. You see, it depends on how you apply the idea.

Well, I just wanted to show you these things, which could be multiplied ad infinitum, to show you how ideas about the national economy gradually developed in the age of the consciousness soul. Opinions always leaned toward one side or the other. Some always believed that national prosperity flourishes best when the national economy is organized individualistically, when individuals are allowed as much freedom as possible. Others believed that this would disadvantage the weaker members of society; that the weaker members must be supported by the state or by associations.

I would have to describe a great deal if I wanted to list everything that has come to light over time. Such economic ideas have emerged in various parts of the civilized world. Those I have described to you, and many others, basically all boiled down to not just thinking about What is the social structure of the world as it has developed so far? They also wanted to know how best to deal with this social structure so that people would not have to live in misery, so that people would have prosperity and the like. Many of those who studied economics tended to want to improve economic life. Utopians and people like the French socialists Saint-Simon, Auguste Comte, Louis Blanc, and others had this tendency in mind. They had the following idea: Until now, because society was left to its own devices, it has developed in such a way that a great difference between rich and poor, between the wealthy and the destitute, has become apparent. This must be changed. To this end, they studied the laws of economics and came up with a wide variety of ideas for changing these things and bringing about some kind of improvement. Some, of course, started from the idea that a kind of paradise, as I mentioned recently, could be created on earth.

However, this thinking about the social structure has taken on a special form among the modern proletariat. And I have already spoken here about the reasons why the proletariat was predestined to develop such views. But I would like to add a few comments on one particular aspect. Certainly, what Karl Marx expressed in his books and in those he wrote together with Friedrich Engels has been modified in many ways. But the modifications are much less significant than the fundamental impulses that actually lie behind these ideas. And despite the fact that this statement can only be applied in a very modified form, one can nevertheless say in general: Across all civilized countries, from the far west to Russia, the proletariat is ruled, if no longer explicitly by Marxist ideas, then by Marxist impulses. In a very peculiar way, thinking about social structure appears in this modern Marxist proletarian thinking.

The ideas I have now developed for you, which have also appeared among bourgeois economists since the beginning of the age of consciousness, are taken up by socialist thinking. However, they are transformed by socialist thinking in the same way that the proletarian, from his proletarian caste, must think according to his opinion. This reveals the peculiarity that this idea—that within the modern capitalist social structure, man must sell his labor power as a proletarian—when further developed theoretically, becomes the driving force of proletarian thinking, giving rise to the question: How can we prevent labor power from being brought onto the market and sold like a commodity? Of course, this impulse is influenced by the view, clearly formulated by Adam Smith and others, that the goods one buys contain stored labor power. It is an immensely plausible idea, an idea that then extends to the conclusion: Yes, what can be done about it? When I buy a skirt, the work that the tailor has put into it, or that of those who were involved in making the skirt, is contained in the skirt: stored labor. The question is therefore not even considered: Can labor be separated from the commodity? — Instead, it is regarded as something, I would say, axiomatic, as something self-evident, that labor is inseparably linked to the commodity. One therefore seeks a social structure that will render this irrefutable fact as harmless as possible for the worker, namely that labor remains linked to the product of labor. It was under this influence that Marxism actually arose, that the belief arose that only by transferring the means of production to the community, that is, by making the community in a certain sense the owner of the means of production, of all the machines and of the land and the means of transportation, that only in this way can one bring about fair remuneration. The question did not arise at all: Can goods be made independent of remuneration? — but rather: How can fair remuneration be achieved if one must axiomatically, as a matter of course, assume that labor flows into goods? — That is the question, and everything else is connected with it. Even the materialistic view of economics and the extreme materialistic view of history are connected with it. As I have already explained to you, these consist in the fact that the modern proletarian thinks: Everything that operates within human culture, all intellectual products, all thought, all politics, everything that is not based on economic processes, is only a superstructure, an ideology that is built on the foundation of what is economically produced. Economics is reality. The way in which man is placed within the economic structure is the reality of human life. What thoughts he then has is determined by his economic context. People who are staunch Marxists, such as Franz Mehring, write about Lessing—and this is just one example—by examining: What was economic life like in the second half of the eighteenth century? How did people manufacture and buy things? What was the relationship between trade and the rest of humanity? How did people think as a result? How did Lessing come about? This particular personality with his achievements, Lessing, is explained by the economic life of the second half of the eighteenth century! Kautsky and others even attempt to explain the emergence of Christianity from this point of view. They examine the economic conditions at the beginning of our era and conclude: Such and such production relations prevailed. This meant that at that time, what they call a kind of communist thinking developed in a certain way, which was then baptized in the name of Jesus Christ. The reality at the beginning of our era is in truth the economic order. Christianity is an ideology, a superstructure, a mirror image, as it were, of our economic order. There is nothing else but economic order. Everything else is floating above it, a mirage, a reflection, nothing real, at most something that—as I have already characterized in earlier lectures—has a retroactive effect on economic conditions, but only to a small extent, via the detour of human processes of a different kind.

These two things work together. The indignation that people have to treat a part of themselves, their labor power, as a commodity, works together with the completely extreme materialistic idea that economic life is the only thing that is real.

Of course, not all people have adopted this view, although millions of people, especially the proletariat, are more or less dominated by these views. But among other people, a different attitude has become common with regard to these things. What is common among the proletariat is not common among other people. When the proletarians have worked their eight or ten or sometimes more hours, they gather together in the evening and discuss this question, have this question presented to them; women's meetings also take place. Each and every one of them is concerned with the nature of the social structure and thinks about it in their own way, listens to the conclusions of those who think about these things, and so on. They know what is going on, in their own way, but they know. In the layer above, which is called the bourgeoisie—you will have to admit this—this is not the case, and after “work is done,” we say this in quotation marks, people occupy themselves with other things. At most, one concerns oneself with the proletariat in such a way—and one then believes one has done a great deal—that one has it played out on stage, prepared by some philistine posing as a poet. But thoughts about the economic order are left to the professors at the universities. They are employed to do that, they do it. Of course, one does not believe in authority, but one swears by what these professors at the universities have thought up about such things; that must be right, of course, because they are paid by the state and are, after all, the people who are there for that purpose. Yes, but you see, a strange economic theory has gradually developed among these professors. When they write books today, they call it the “historical school.” They deal with the mercantilists, the physiocrats, Adam Smith, socialism, anarchism, and so on, and then their own views; that is the “historical school.” They ask themselves: How are we supposed to come up with ideas about how to do things? Truly, these people are helpless in this regard. They cannot bring themselves to engage in the kind of thinking that pushes for ideas about how to bring about a particular social structure. Such petty bourgeois as, say, Lujo Brentano or Schmoller or Roscher, do not even think of putting their thinking into action, but believe that one must study phenomena as the natural scientist does. Such a person lets phenomena run their course and studies them. He simply studies the historical development of humanity, perhaps even the historical development of people's ideas about their economy. One describes what is there. At most, one does it like Lujo Brentano: if one does not want to observe it in one's own country, one travels to a country with a representative economy, such as England, conducts research there, and then describes the relationship between employers and employees and so on. One learns to recognize that there are rich people, how credit is acquired, how capital works, that there is misery, that there are people who have nothing, that some have nothing to eat, more or less due to this or that circumstance. But then people say: Yes, science does not have the task of showing how things should develop, but only of pointing out how they do develop. But what, after all, becomes of such a science, which is nevertheless concerned with practical life, if it merely observes how things develop? It is like wanting to train a painter and telling him: Above all, go and see all kinds of painters and observe how one does it well, another badly, and so on, but don't do anything yourself! In such a field, the matter immediately becomes paradoxical; but it really is comparable to the other. It is enough to drive one out of one's skin – forgive the expression – when one really begins to consider what is being done today, not achieved, but rather botched, when the scientific method attempts to apply itself to such things as economics or the like. Nothing comes of it because, fundamentally, the premises are completely absurd. At best, this group gives rise to so-called armchair socialists who, based on their observations of the status quo, come to the conclusion that something must be done. And then laws are passed that are supposed to remedy this or that.

But it is precisely this helplessness that has contributed to bringing about this situation. And it would be cowardly today not to point out that what today's humanity, which naturally does not worship authority, allows itself to be told in this area, with which it declares itself satisfied, is in many cases to blame for the chaos into which we have fallen. These things are so serious that they really must be addressed in their true form. Then the question arises: What is at work here? Why has it all come to this? Why do such fluctuating ideas have such an effect on one of the most important areas of human life, as I have explained to you?

Let us consider such an idea, which is illusory but extremely effective. Let us consider the Marxist idea, modified for my sake, which is essentially the idea of today's professors: Only the economy is real, only the economic structure is real; everything else is ideology, superstructure, a mirage that has developed around it. This is something highly remarkable: the absolute disbelief in everything that human beings can produce as spirit from all the ideas that have developed since the dawn of the age of the conscious soul. This means that people are increasingly drawn to what is known externally, what is tangibly present to the senses. They flee from and avoid the rest. And in this flight, in this avoidance, not only social ideas but also social feelings and ultimately social events have developed in our time, and will continue to develop unless the call for a truly spiritual-scientific understanding of this fact is heard.

What is the underlying cause of this? The underlying cause is that we have just entered the age of the consciousness soul, that we have been in it since the fifteenth century, and that this development within the age of the consciousness soul, this urge of human beings toward the awakening of the consciousness soul, makes it necessary that human beings are approaching more and more a point in their development where they actually want to flee — out of “counter-instincts.” An essential factor will be that modern human beings overcome this flight instinct; they want to flee from something into which they must nevertheless enter. I told you recently, when I last spoke here, that across the different national regions — the West, the middle countries, the East — there are also differences in the way human beings approach the guardian of the threshold when they enter the spiritual world. A movement toward experiencing such experiences as can be consciously had with the guardian of the threshold but which must be made more or less instinctively by human beings in the age of the consciousness soul — being drawn toward the experiences with the guardian of the threshold in a certain, albeit external, form — is what acts as an impulse, an instinct, a drive in modern human beings, and what they flee from. They are afraid of arriving where they should actually arrive.

This is very natural in the modern development of human beings. Take what I presented earlier as the external characteristic of modern striving. Human beings strive to recognize what they are as human beings, what they are worth as human beings, what power they have, what their dignity is as human beings. Human beings strive to see themselves as human beings, to finally arrive at an image of their own being. One cannot arrive at an image of the human being if one wants to remain within the sensory world, for the human being is not exhausted in the sensory world; the human being is not merely a sensory being. In the ages of instinctive development, when one does not ask about an image of man or about human dignity or human power, one can pass over the fact that if one wants to know man, one must go out of the sensory world and look into the spiritual world, that one must at least in some form intellectually acquaint oneself with the supersensible world in our age of consciousness. But then the same thing that the initiate must consciously overcome works unconsciously. Unconsciously, this fear of the unknown that must be considered still works in our contemporaries and in the people whose social thoughts I have described to you. Fear, despondency, cowardice—these are the things that dominate modern humanity. And when modern humanity says that economics is the tangible thing that brings everything about, this view has arisen because people are afraid of what is invisible, what is not tangible. People do not want to approach it, they want to avoid it, they turn it into ideology, into a mirage. And they turn it into ideology, into a mirage, because they are afraid of it. The modern social worldview is a point of fear and anxiety in relation to the points I have characterized for you. Some people may appear outwardly courageous in their pursuit of this modern social worldview, but on the one hand, they may be courageous, yet on the other hand, they are afraid of the spiritual, which must confront them in some form in which they want to get to know people, and they cowardly retreat from it. A product of fear, a product of anxiety, that is what comes to light in modern socialist worldviews.

Things must be viewed from this perspective. For modern man must learn three things, because he is naturally led to these three things, differentiated according to the West, the Middle, and the East, as I characterized them for you last time. But he is naturally led to these three things in some form. Even if only the initiated can see what is present in these three points, every modern man must gradually feel, sense, and take into his intellect—even if not into his visual perception—if he wants to penetrate the economic structure. First, modern man must gain a clear sense or at least a clear intellectual idea of the forces that are the forces of decline, the destructive forces in the universe. Among the forces that people like to pursue — and they are mistaken because they pursue them only with the sympathies of liking — are precisely the constructive forces. People always want to build, build, build. But in the world there is not only evolution or construction, there is also involution or destruction. We ourselves carry destruction within us. Our developed nervous system, our brain system, is in a state of constant destruction. Destruction is in the world. Man must become familiar with these forces of destruction. He must say to himself, without prejudice and without bias: It is precisely on the path that is developing in the age in which the consciousness soul is to awaken fully that the forces of destruction are most effective. These forces of destruction sometimes concentrate and consolidate, and then something like the last four and a half years develops. In a concentrated state, something that is always present is revealed to humanity. But this does not have to remain unconscious and instinctive; it must become fully known, especially in this age. The destructive forces, the forces of death, the paralyzing forces — human beings like to turn their faces away from them; but in doing so, they blind themselves and do not learn to cooperate in evolution because they flee from the destructive forces.

The second thing that human beings must become familiar with, and which they in turn flee, is that in this age of intellectual development, that is, development in the age of the consciousness soul, human beings must inevitably come to seek, as it were, a new center of gravity for their being. Instinctive development has given them a center of gravity, even in their thoughts. They believe they stand firm on their views, on their ideas, which they have acquired through blood or descent or in some other way. From now on, human beings cannot do this. They must detach themselves from what they have stood firm on, from what has developed instinctively. Man must, in a sense, stand at the edge of the abyss, must feel the emptiness, the abyss beneath him, because he must find the center of his being within himself. Man shrinks from this, he is afraid of it.

And the third is this: if man is to develop toward the future, he must come to know, in all its power, the impulse of selfishness, of egoism. Our age is suited to making it clear to humans that, if they give in to their nature, they are selfish beings. We must first explore all the sources of egoism in human nature in order to overcome egoism. Love only appears as the counterpart to self-love. One must cross the abyss of self-love if one wants to know what is to permeate the social structure of the present and the future as social warmth, especially if one wants to know it not only in theory but in full practice. Approaching this feeling, which the initiate clearly sees in the guardian of the threshold when entering the supersensible world, fills people with fear, as they realize that there is no other way to enter the age that must necessarily bring forth a social structure than through love that is not self-love, but love for other people, interest in other people. People experience this as something burning, something that consumes them, something that robs them of their very essence by taking away their self-love, their right to self-love. And just as they flee from the supersensible, which they fear because it is unknown to them, so they flee from love because it is a burning fire to them. And just as people in the age in which we must prepare for spiritual impulses blindfold themselves and stop their ears to the truth of the supersensible, for example by pointing out in Marxism and in today's proletarianized thinking that we must rely on the tangible in order to distract ourselves from the supersensible, just as they pursue the opposite of what what lies in the real tendency of human development in this area, they do the same in the area of love. This is even evident in the “words of tendency.” Ideals are set up that are the opposite of what actually lies in human development and must be strived for.

When the first and most significant manifestation of the modern proletarian view of life, the Communist Manifesto, appeared in 1848, Karl Marx's Communist Manifesto already contained the words that can now be found as a motto on almost every socialist book and brochure: “Proletarians of all countries, unite!”

If one has even a little sense of reality, one must come to a precise but strangely paradoxical conclusion about these words. What does it mean: “Proletarians of all countries, unite!”? It means: Work together, work with each other, be brothers to each other, be comrades! — That is love! — Let love work among you! — The tendency appears tumultuous, but how? — Proletarians, become aware that you are separated from humanity, hate those who are not proletarians, let hatred be the impulse of your union! — In a strange way, love and hatred are linked together; union is sought out of hatred, the opposite of union! This is not noticed because today we are far removed from linking our thoughts with reality. But it is the fear of love, which is wounded but at the same time avoided because we shy away from it, recoil from it as from a consuming fire, by emphasizing precisely such words and making them the motto of the social movement.

Thus, only a spiritual-scientific understanding of what is real can provide insight into what is at work in the present and what one must know in order to truly be conscious of this present. It is not so easy to follow what is pulsating in humanity today. Spiritual science is necessary for this pursuit. This should not be overlooked. And only those who take these things seriously enough are correctly positioned in this spiritual scientific movement.